Читать книгу The Analogy of Religion to the Constitution and Course of Nature - Butler Joseph, Joseph Butler - Страница 4
Conspectus of the Analogy
PART I
ОглавлениеCHAPTER I
A FUTURE LIFE
Will not discuss the subject of identity; but will consider what analogy suggests from changes which do not destroy; and thus see whether it is not probable that we shall live hereafter.
I. The probabilities that we shall survive death.
1. It is a law of nature that creatures should exist in different stages, and in various degrees of perfection.
– Worms turn into flies.
– Eggs are hatched into birds.
– Our own present state is as different from our state in the womb, as two states of the same being can be.
– That we shall hereafter exist in a state as different from the present as the present is from our state in the womb, is according to analogy.
2. We now have capacities for happiness, action, misery, &c., and there is always a probability that things will continue as they are, except when experience gives us reason to think they will be altered. This is a general law; and is our only natural reason for expecting the continuance of any thing.
3. There is no reason to apprehend that death will destroy us.
If there was, it would arise from the nature of death; or from the analogy of nature.
1.) Not from the nature of death.
– We know not what death is.
– But only some of its effects.
– These effects do not imply the destruction of the living agent.
– We know little of what the exercise of our powers depends upon; and nothing of what the powers themselves depend on.
– We may be unable to exercise our powers, and yet not lose them —e. g. sleep, swoon.
2.) Not from analogy.
– Reason shows no connection between death and our destruction.
– We have no faculties by which to trace any being beyond it.
– The possession of living powers, up to the very moment when our faculties cease to be able to trace them, is a probability of their continuing.
– We have already survived wonderful changes.
– To live after death is analogous to the course of nature.
II. Presumptions against a future life.
1. That death destroys us.
Ans. 1. This is an assumption that we are compound and material beings, and hence discerptible; which is not true.
1.) Consciousness is a single, indivisible power, and of course the subject of it must be.
2.) The material body is not ourself.
3.) We can easily conceive of our having more limbs, or of a different kind, or of having more or fewer senses, or of having no bodies at all, or of hereafter animating these same bodies, remodelled.
4.) The dissolution of a succession of new and strange bodies, would have no tendency to destroy us.
Ans. 2. Though the absolute simplicity of the living being cannot be proved by experiment, yet facts lead us so to conclude. We lose limbs, &c. Our bodies were once very small, but we might, then, have lost part of them. There is a constant destruction and renewal going on.
1.) Thus we see that no certain bulk is necessary to our existence, and unless it were proved that there is, and that it is larger than an indissoluble atom, there is no reason to presume that death destroys us, even if we are discerptible.
2.) The living agent is not an internal material organism, which dies with the body. Because
– Our only ground for this presumption is our relation to other systems of matter. But we see these are not necessary to us.
– It will not do to say that lost portions of the body were not essential– who is to determine?
– The relation between the living agent, and the most essential parts of the body, is only one by which they mutually affect each other.
3.) If we regard our body as made up of organs of sense, we come to the same result.
– We see with the eyes, just as we do with glasses. The eye is not a recipient, any more than a telescope.
– It is not pretended that vision, hearing, &c. can be traced clear up to the percipient; but so far as we can trace perceptions, the organ does not perceive.
– In dreams we perceive without organs.
– When we lose a limb we do not lose the directing power; we could move a new one, if it could be made, or a wooden one. But the limb cut off has no power of moving.
– Thus, our loss of the organs of perception and motion, not being the destruction of the power, there is no ground to think that the destruction of other organs or instruments would destroy us.
Objection. These observations apply equally to brutes.
Ans. 1. Be it so. Perhaps they are immortal: – may hereafter improve: we know not what latent powers they may have.
1.) The human being at one period looks as little likely to make great intellectual attainments; for a long time he has capacities for virtue and religion, but cannot use them.
2.) Many persons go out of the world who never became able to exercise these capacities; e. g. infants.
Ans. 2. If brutes were immortal, it does not prove them to be moral agents.
1.) It may be necessary, for aught we know, that there should be living creatures not moral agents, nor rational.
2.) All difficulties as to what would become of them, are founded in our ignorance.
2. That our souls, though not material, so depend upon the bodily structure, that we cannot survive its destruction.
Ans. 1. Reason, memory, &c. do not depend on the body, as perceptions by the senses do. Death may destroy those instruments, and yet not destroy the powers of reflection.
Ans. 2. Human beings exist, here, in two very different states, each having its own laws: sensation and reflection. By the first we feel; by the second we reason and will.
1.) Nothing which we know to be destroyed at death, is necessary to reflecting on ideas formerly received.
2.) Though the senses act like scaffolds, or levers, to bring in ideas, yet when once in, we can reflect, &c. without their aid.
Ans. 3. There are diseases which prove fatal, &c., yet do not, in any part of their course, impair the intellect; and this indicates that they do not destroy it.
1.) In the diseases alluded to, persons have their reflective power, in full, the very moment before death.
2.) Now, why should a disease, at a certain degree, utterly destroy powers which were not even affected by it, up to that point?
3. That death at least suspends our reflective powers, or interrupts our continuing to exist in the like state of reflection which we do now.
Ans. There appears so little connection between our powers of sensation and our powers of reflection that we cannot presume that what might destroy the former, could even suspend the latter.
1.) We daily see reason, memory, &c. exercised without any assistance, that we know of, from our bodies.
2.) Seeing them in lively exercise to the last, we must infer that death is not a discontinuance of their exercise, nor of the enjoyments and sufferings of such exercise.
3.) Our posthumous life may be but a going on, with additions. Like the change at our birth – which produced not a suspension of the faculties we had before, nor a total change in our state of life; but a continuance of both, with great alterations.
4.) Death may but at once put us into a higher state of life, as our birth did; our relation to bodily organs may be the only hinderance to our entering a higher condition of the reflective powers.
5.) Were we even sure that death would suspend our intellectual powers, it would not furnish even the lowest probability that it would destroy them.
Objec. From the analogy of plants.
Ans. This furnishes poets with apt illustrations of our frailty, but affords no proper analogy. Plants are destitute of perception and action, and this is the very matter in question.
REMARKS
1. It has been shown, that confining ourselves to what we know, we see no probability of ever ceasing to be: – it cannot be concluded from the reason of the thing: – nor from the analogy of nature.
2. We are therefore to go upon the belief of a future existence.
3. Our going into new scenes and conditions, is just as natural as our coming into the world.
4. Our condition may naturally be a social one.
5. The advantages of it may naturally be bestowed, according to some fixed law, in proportion to one’s degrees in virtue.
1.) Perhaps not so much as now by society; but by God’s more immediate action.
2.) Yet this will be no less natural, i. e. stated, fixed, or settled.
3.) Our notions of what is natural, are enlarged by greater knowledge of God and his works.
4.) There may be some beings in the world, to whom the whole of Christianity is as natural as the visible course of nature seems to us.
6. These probabilities of a future life, though they do not satisfy curiosity, answer all the purposes of religion, as well as demonstration.
1.) Even a demonstration of a future state, would not demonstrate religion, but would be reconcilable with atheism.
2.) But as religion implies a future state, any presumption against such a state, would be a presumption against religion.
3.) The foregoing observations remove all presumptions of that sort, and prove to a great probability, a fundamental doctrine of religion.
CHAPTER II
THE GOVERNMENT OF GOD BY REWARDS AND PUNISHMENTS
The question of a future life is rendered momentous by our capacity for happiness and misery.
Especially if that happiness or misery depends on our present conduct.
We should feel the deepest solicitude on this subject.
And that if there were no proof of a future life and interest, other than the probabilities just discussed.
I. In the present world our pleasures and pains are, to a great extent, in our own power
1. We see them to be consequences of our actions.
2. And we can foresee these consequences.
3. Our desires are not gratified, without the right kind of exertion.
4. By prudence we may enjoy life; rashness, or even neglect may make us miserable.
5. Why this is so is another matter.
1.) It may be impossible to be otherwise.
2.) Or it may be best on the whole.
3.) Or God’s plan may be to make only the good happy.
4.) Or the whole plan may be incomprehensible to us.
Objec. It may be said “this is only the course of nature.”
Ans. It is granted: but
1. The course of nature is but the will of God. We admit that God is the natural governor of the world: and must not turn round and deny it because his government is uniform.
2. Our natural foresight of the consequences of actions, is his appointment.
3. The consequences themselves, are his appointment.
4. Our ability to foresee these consequences, is God’s instruction how we are to act.
Objec. By this reasoning we are instructed to gratify our appetites, and such gratification is our reward for so doing.
Ans. Certainly not. Foreseen pleasures and pains are proper motives to action in general; but we may, in particular cases, damage ourselves by indulgence. Our eyes are made to see with, but not to look at every thing: – for instance the sun.
It follows, from what has been said, that
II. We are, now, actually under God’s government, in the strictest sense
1. Admitting that there is a God, it is not so much a matter of speculation, as of experience, that he governs us.
2. The annexing of pleasures and pains to certain actions, and giving notice them, is the very essence of government.
3. Whether by direct acts upon us, or by contriving a general plan, does not affect the argument.
1.) If magistrates could make laws which should execute themselves, their government would be far more perfect than it is.
2.) God’s making fire burn us, is as much an instance of government, as if he directly inflicted the burn, whenever we touched fire.
4. Hence the analogy of nature shows nothing to render incredible the Bible doctrine of God’s rewarding or punishing according to our actions.
Additional remarks on Punishment
As men object chiefly to future punishment, it is proper to show further that the course of administration, as to present punishment, is analogous to what religion teaches as to the future.
Indeed they add credibility to it.
And ought to raise the most serious apprehension.
I. Circumstances to be observed touching present punishments
1. They often follow acts which produce present pleasure or advantage.
2. The sufferings often far exceed the pleasure or advantage.
3. They often follow remotely.
4. After long delay they often come suddenly.
5. As those remote effects are not certainly foreseen, they may not be thought of at the time; or if so, there is a hope of escaping.
6. There are opportunities of advantage, which if neglected do not recur.
7. Though, in some cases, men who have sinned up to a certain point, may retrieve their affairs, yet in many cases, reformation is of no avail.
8. Inconsiderateness is often as disastrous as wilful wrong-doing.
9. As some punishments by civil government, are capital, so are some natural punishments.
1.) Seem intended to remove the offender out of the way.
2.) Or as an example to others.
II. These things are not accidental, but proceed from fixed laws
1. They are matters of daily experience.
2. Proceed from the general laws, by which the world is governed.
III. They so closely resemble what religion teaches, as to future punishment, that both might be expressed in the same words
e. g. Proverbs, ch. i.
The analogy sufficiently answers all objections against the Scripture doctrine of future punishment, such as
1.) That our frailty or temptations annihilate the guilt of vice.
2.) Or the objection from necessity.
3.) Or that the Almighty cannot be contradicted.
4.) Or that he cannot be offended.
REMARKS
1. Such reflections are terrific, but ought to be stated and considered.
2. Disregard of a hereafter cannot be justified by any thing short of a demonstration of atheism. Even skeptical doctrines afford no justification.
3. There is no pretence of reason for presuming that the licentious will not find it better for them that they had never been born.
CHAPTER III
MORAL GOVERNMENT OF GOD
As the structure of the world shows intelligence, so the mode of distributing pleasure and pain, shows government. That is, God’s natural government, such as a king exercises over his subjects.
But this does not, at first sight, determine what is the moral character of such government.
I. What is a moral or righteous government?
1. Not mere rewarding and punishing.
2. But doing this according to character.
3. The perfection of moral government is doing this exactly.
Objec. God is simply and absolutely benevolent.
Ans. Benevolence, infinite in degree, would dispose him to produce the greatest possible happiness, regardless of behaviour. This would rob God of other attributes; and should not be asserted unless it can be proved. And whether it can be proved is not the point now in hand.
The question is not whether there may not be, in the universe, beings to whom he manifests absolute benevolence, which might not be incompatible with justice; but whether he treats us so.
4. It must be owned to be vastly difficult, in such a disordered world, to estimate with exactness the overplus of happiness on the side of virtue: and there may be exceptions to the rule. But it is far from being doubtful that on the whole, virtue is happier than vice, in this world.
II. The beginnings of a righteous administration, are seen in nature
1. It has been proved (ch. ii.) that God governs: and it is reasonable to suppose that he would govern righteously.
1.) Any other rule of government would be harder to account for.
2.) The Bible doctrine that hereafter the good shall be happy, and the wicked miserable, is no more than an expectation that a method of government, now begun, shall be carried on.
2. The opposite consequences of prudence and rashness, show a right constitution of nature; and our ability to foresee and control these consequences, shows that we are under moral law.
3. God has so constructed society that vice, to a great degree, is actually punished by it.
1.) Without this, society could not exist.
2.) This is God’s government, through society; and is as natural, as society.
3.) Since the course of things is God’s appointment, men are unavoidably accountable for their behaviour.
Objec. Society often punishes good actions, and rewards wickedness.
Ans. 1. This is not necessary, and consequently not natural.
2. Good actions are never punished by society as good, but because considered bad.
4. By the course of nature, virtue is rewarded, and vice punished, as such, which proves a moral government; as will be seen if we rightly distinguish between actions and their qualities.
1.) An action may produce present gratification though it be wrong: in which case the gratification is in the act, not the morality of it: in other cases the enjoyment consists wholly in the quality of virtuousness.
2.) Vice is naturally attended with uneasiness, apprehension, vexation, remorse, &c.
– This is a very different feeling from that produced by mere misfortune.
– Men comfort themselves under misfortune, that it was not their own fault.
3.) Honest and good men are befriended as such.
4.) Injuries are resented as implying fault; and good offices are regarded with gratitude on account of the intention, even when they fail to benefit us.
– This is seen in family government, where children are punished for falsehood, fretfulness, &c., though no one is hurt.
– And also in civil government, where the absence or presence of ill intention goes far in determining the penalty of wrong-doing.
5.) The whole course of the world, in all ages and relations, turns much upon approbation and disapprobation.
6.) The very fact of our having a moral nature, is a proof of our being under God’s moral government.
– We are placed in a condition which unavoidably operates on our moral nature.
– Hence it arises that reward to virtue and reprobation of vice, as such, is a rule, never inverted. If it be thought that there are instances to the contrary, (which is not so,) they are evidently monstrous.
– The degree in which virtue and vice receive proper returns, is not the question now, but only the thing itself, in some degree.
7.) It is admitted that virtue sometimes suffers, and vice prospers; but this is disorder, and not the order of nature.
8.) It follows, that we have in the government of the world, a declaration from God, for virtue and against vice. So far as a man is true to virtue, is he on the side of the divine administration. Such a man must have a sense of security, and a hope of something better.
5. This hope is confirmed by observing that virtue has necessary tendencies beyond their present effects.
1.) These are very obvious with regard to individuals.
2.) Are as real, though not so patent, in regard to society.
– The power of a society under the direction of virtue, tends to prevail over power not so directed, just as power under direction of reason, tends to prevail over brute force.
– As this may not be conceded, we will notice how the case stands, as to reason:
· Length of time, and proper opportunity, are necessary for reason to triumph over brutes.
· Rational beings, disunited, envious, unjust, and treacherous, may be overcome by brutes, uniting themselves by instinct: but this would be an inverted order of things.
– A like tendency has virtue to produce superiority.
· By making the good of society, the object of every member of it.
· By making every one industrious in his own sphere.
· By uniting all in one bond of veracity and justice.
3.) If the part of God’s government which we see, and the part we do not see, make up one scheme, then we see a tendency in virtue to superiority.
4.) But to produce that superiority there must be
– A force proportioned to the obstacles.
– Sufficient lapse of time.
– A fair field of trial; such as extent of time, adequate occasions, and opportunities for the virtuous to unite.
5.) These things are denied to virtue in this life, so that its tendencies, though real, are hindered.
6.) But it may have all requisite advantages hereafter.
– Eternity will be lasting enough.
– Good men will unite; as they cannot do now, scattered over the earth, and ignorant of one another.
– Other orders of virtuous beings will join; for the very nature of virtue is a bond of union.
7.) The tendency of such an order of things, so far as seen by vicious beings in any part of the universe, would be to the amendment of all who were capable of it, and their recovery to virtue.
8.) All this goes to show that the hinderances to virtue are contingent, and that its beneficial tendencies are God’s declarations in its favor.
9.) If the preceding considerations are thought to be too speculative, we may easily come to the same result by reflecting on the supremacy which any earthly nation would attain, by entire virtue for many ages.
REMARKS
Consider now the general system of religion. The government of the world is one; it is moral; virtue shall in the end prevail over wickedness; and to see the importance and fitness of such an arrangement we have only to consider what would be the state of things, if vice had these advantages, or virtue the contrary.
Objec. Why may not things be now going on in other worlds, and continue always to go on in this world, in the same mixed and disordered state as at present?
Ans. We are not proving that God’s moral government is perfect, or the truth of religion, but only seeing what there is in the course of nature, to confirm it, supposing it to be known. Were there nothing to judge by, but the present distribution of pleasure and pain, we should have no ground to conclude that hereafter we should be rewarded or punished exactly according to our deserts. But even then there would be no indication that vice is better than virtue. Still the preceding observations confirm the doctrine of future retribution; for,
1.) They show that the Author of nature is not indifferent to virtue and vice.
2.) That future distributive justice would differ not in kind, but in degree only, from God’s present government. It would be the effect, towards which we see the tendency.
3.) That higher rewards and punishments may be hereafter.
4.) That we should expect it to be so; because the tendencies of vice and virtue are immutable, while the hinderances are only artificial.
SUMMARY
[This enumerates the steps of the argument, in the foregoing chapter, in as condensed a form as possible.]
CHAPTER IV
OF A STATE OF PROBATION
The doctrine of probation comprehends several particulars. But the most common notion is that our future interests are depending; and depending on ourselves. And that we have opportunities for both good and bad conduct, and temptations to each.
This is not exactly the same as our being under moral government; for it implies allurement to evil, and difficulties in being good.
Hence needs to be considered by itself.
Doctrine. The natural government of God, in this world, puts us on trial as to the things of this world; and so implies, what religion teaches, that his moral government puts us on trial as to a future world.
I. So far as we are tempted to do what will damage our future temporal interests, so far we are under probation as to those interests
1. The annexing of pleasures and pains to actions, as good or bad, and enabling us to foresee their effect, implies that our interests, in part at least, depend on ourselves.
2. We often blame ourselves and others for evils, as resulting from misconduct.
3. It is very certain that we often miss possible good, and incur evils, not for want of knowing better, but through our fault.
4. Every one speaks of the hazards of young persons, from other causes than ignorance.
II. These natural or temporal trials are analogous to our moral and religious trial
1. In both cases, what constitutes the trial, is either in our circumstances or in our nature.
1.) Some would do right but for violent or extraordinary temptations.
2.) Others will seek evil, and go out of their way after wicked indulgence, when there are no external temptations.
3.) But even those who err through temptation, must have that within which makes them susceptible of temptation.
4.) So that we are in a like state of probation with respect to both present and future interests.
2. If we proceed to observe how mankind behave in both capacities, we see the same analogy.
1.) Some scarcely look beyond the present gratification.
2.) Some are driven by their passions against their better judgment and feeble resolutions.
3.) Some shamelessly go on in open vice.
4.) Some persist in wrong-doing, even under strong apprehensions of future misery.
3. The analogy is no less plain in regard to the influence of others upon us.
1.) Bad example.
2.) Wrong education.
3.) Corruptions of religion.
4.) General prevalence of mistakes as to true happiness.
4. In both cases negligence and folly bring difficulty as well as vice.
III. The disadvantages we labor under from our fallen and disordered state, are the same, in relation to both earthly and future interests
This disadvantage affords no ground of complaint; for,
1. We may manage to pass our days in comfort and peace.
2. And so may we obtain the security and comfort of religion.
3. We might as well complain that we are not a higher order of beings.
REMARKS
1. It is thus proved that the state of trial, which religion says we are in, is credible; for it exactly corresponds to what we see.
1.) If from birth till death we were in a constant security of enjoyment, without care or correctness, it would be a presumption against religion.
2.) It might, if we had no experience, be urged that an infinitely good Being would not expose us to the hazard of misery. This is indeed a difficulty, and must remain so; but still the course of nature is as it is.
3.) The miseries which we bring on ourselves are no more unavoidable than our deportment.
2. It has been proved that we are in danger of miscarrying as to our interests, both present and future.
3. The sum of the whole is, that as we do not have present enjoyments and honors forced upon us, in spite of misconduct, so this may be the case, as to that chief and final good which religion proposes.
CHAPTER V
PROBATION INTENDED FOR MORAL DISCIPLINE AND IMPROVEMENT
Why we should be placed in the condition spoken of in the last chapter, is a question which cannot be answered. It may be that we could not understand, if told. And if we could, it might injure us to know, just now. It certainly is consistent with God’s righteous government.
Religion tells us that we are so placed in order to become qualified for a better state.
This, though a very partial answer to the inquiry why we are so placed, answers an infinitely more important question, – viz.: What is our business here?
I. We are placed in this state of trial, for our improvement in virtue, as the requisite qualification for future security and happiness
1. Every creature is designed for a particular way of life.
1.) Happiness depends on the congruity between a creature’s nature and its circumstances.
2.) Man’s character might be so changed as to make him incapable of happiness on earth.
3.) Or he might be placed, without changing his nature, in a world where he must be wretched, for want of the proper objects to answer to his desires.
4.) So that without determining what is the future condition of good men, we know there must be necessary qualifications to make us capable of enjoying it.
2. Human beings are so constituted as to become fit for new and different conditions.
1.) We not only acquire ideas, but store them up.
2.) We can become more expert in any kind of action.
3.) And can make settled alterations in our tempers.
4.) We can form habits– both bodily and mental.
As these operate in producing radical changes in human character, we will look for a moment at the process.
– Neither perceptions, nor knowledge, are habits; though necessary to forming them.
– There are habits of perception, however, and habits of action: the former are passive, the latter active.
– Habits of body are produced by external acts, and habits of mind by the exertion of principles; i. e. carrying them out.
– Resolutions to do well are acts, and may help towards forming good habits. But mere theorizing, and forming pictures in the mind, not only do not help, but may harden the mind to a contrary course.
– Passive impressions, by repetition grow weaker. Thus familiarity with danger lessens fear.
– Hence active habits may be formed and strengthened, by acting according to certain motives or excitements, which grow less sensibly felt and less and less felt, as the habit strengthens.
· Thus the sight of distress excites the passive emotion of pity, and the active principle of benevolence. But inquiring out cases of distress in order to relieve them, causes diminished sensitiveness at the sight of misery, and stronger benevolence and aptitude in relieving it.
· So admonition, experience, and example, if acted upon, produce good; if not, harden.
5.) The formation of a habit may be imperceptible and even inexplicable, but the thing itself is matter of certain experience.
6.) A habit once formed, the action becomes easy and often pleasurable: opposite inclinations grow weaker: difficulties less: and occasions more frequent.
7.) Thus, a new character, in several respects, is formed.
3. We should not have these capacities for improvement and for the reconstruction of character, if it were not necessary.
1.) They are necessary, even as to this life.
– We are not qualified, at first, for mature life: understanding and strength come gradually.
– If we had them in full, at birth, we should at first be distracted and bewildered, and our faculties would be of no use previous to experience. Ignorant of any employment, we could not provide for ourselves.
– So that man is an unformed, unfinished creature, even as to this world, till he acquire knowledge, experience, and habits.
2.) Provision is made for our acquiring, in youth, the requisite qualities for manhood.
– Children learn, from their very birth,
· The nature and use of objects.
· The subordinations of domestic life.
· The rules of life.
– Some of this learning is acquired so insensibly, as to seem like instinct, but some requires great care and labor, and the doing of things we are averse to.
– According as we act during this formative period, is our character formed; and our capacity for various stations in society determined.
– Early opportunities lost, cannot be recovered.
3.) Our state of discipline throughout this life, for another, is exactly of the same kind: and comprehended under one general law.
– If we could not see how the present discipline fitted us for a higher life, it would be no objection.
· We do not know how food, sleep, &c. enlarges the child’s body; nor would we expect such a result, prior to experience.
· Nor do children understand the need of exercise, temperance, restraint, &c.
– We thus see a general analogy of Providence indicating that the present life is preparatory.
4. If virtue is a necessary qualification for future happiness, then we see our need of the moral culture of our present state.
1.) Analogy indicates that our future state will be social.
– Nature furnishes no shadow of unreasonableness in the Scripture doctrine that this future community will be under the more immediate government of God.
– Nor the least proof that its members will not require the exercise of veracity, justice, &c. towards each other; and that character which results from the practice of such virtues.
– Certainly the universe is under moral government; and a virtuous character must, in some way, be a condition of happiness in that state.
2.) We are deficient, and in danger of deviating from what is right.
– We have desires for outward objects.
– The times, degrees, &c. of gratifying these desires, are, of right, subject to the control of the moral principle.
– But that principle neither excites them, nor prevents their being excited.
– They may exist, when they cannot be lawfully gratified, or gratified at all.
– When the desire exists, and the gratification is unlawful, we are tempted.
3.) The only security is the principle within.
– The strengthening of this lessens the danger.
– It may be strengthened, by discipline and exercise.
· Noting examples.
· Attending to the right, and not to preference.
· Considering our true interests.
– When improved, it becomes, in proportion to its strength, our security from the dangers of natural propensions.
– Virtue, become habitual by discipline, is improved virtue; and improved virtue must produce increased happiness, if the government of the world is moral.
4.) Even creatures made upright may fall.
– The fall of an upright being, is not accounted for by the nature of liberty; for that would only be saying that an event happened because it might happen.
– But from the very nature of propensions.
– A finitely perfect being would have propensions corresponding to its surroundings; its understanding; and its moral sense; and all these in due proportions.
– Such a being would have propensions, though the object might not be present, or the indulgence might be contrary to its moral sense; and this would have some tendency, however small, to induce gratification.
– The tendency would be increased by the frequency of occasions; and yet more by the least indulgence, even in thought; till, under peculiar conjunctures, it would become effect.
– The first transgression might so utterly disorder the constitution, and change the proportions of forces, as to lead to a repetition of irregularities; and hence to the construction of bad habits, and a depraved character.
5.) On the contrary, a finitely perfect being may attain higher virtue, and more security, by obeying the moral principle.
– For the danger would lessen, by the increased submissiveness of propensions.
– The moral principle would gain force by exercise.
6.) Thus vice is not only criminal, but degrading; and virtue is not only right, but improving.
– The degree of improvement may be such that the danger of sinning may be almost infinitely lessened.
– Yet the security may always be the habits formed in a state of discipline; making such a state altogether fit and necessary.
7.) This course of reasoning is vastly stronger when applied to fallen and corrupt creatures.
– The upright need improvement; the fallen must be renewed.
– Discipline is expedient for the one; necessary for the other; and of a severer sort.
II. The present world is peculiarly fit for such discipline as we need
1. Surrounding evils tend to produce moderation, practical knowledge, &c. very different from a mere speculative knowledge of our liability to vice and misery.
2. Our experience in this world, with right views and practice, may leave eternal impressions for good.
3. Every act of self-government in the exercise of virtue, must, from the very make of our nature, form habits of virtue, and a more intense virtuous principle.
4. Resolute and persevering resistance to particular and violent temptations, is a continued act of virtue, and that in a higher degree than if the seduction were transient and weak.
5. Self-denial is not essential to virtue, but is almost essential to discipline and improvement.
1.) Because actions materially virtuous, which have no difficulty, but agree with our inclinations, may be done merely from inclination, and so not be really virtuous.
2.) But when they are done in face of danger and difficulty, virtuousness is increased, and confirmed into a habit.
Objec. 1. As our intellectual or physical powers may be overtasked, so may our moral.
Ans. This may be so in exceptional cases, but it does not confute the argument. In general, it holds good. All that is intended to be proved is, that this world is intended to be a state of improvement, and is fitted for it.
1.) Some sciences which of themselves are highly improving, require a trying measure of attention, which some will not submit to.
2.) It is admitted that this world disciplines many to vice: but this viciousness of many is the very thing which makes the world a virtuous discipline to good men. The whole end in placing mankind as they are we know not; but these things are evident – the virtues of some are exercised: – and so exercised as to be improved: and improved beyond what they would be in a perfectly virtuous community.
3.) That all, or even the generality, do not improve, is no proof that their improvement was not intended. Of seeds and animals not one in a million comes to perfection; yet such as do, evidently answer an end for which they were designed. The appearance of waste in regard to seeds, &c. is just as unaccountable, as the ruin of moral agents.
Objec. 2. Rectitude arising from hope and fear, is only the discipline of self-love.
Ans. Obedience is obedience, though prompted by hope or fear: and a course of such obedience, forms a habit of it: and distinct habits of various virtues, by repressing inclination whenever justice, veracity, &c. require.
Beside, veracity, justice, regard to God’s authority, and self-interest, are coincident; and each, separately, a just principle. To begin a good life from either of them, and persist, produces that very character which corresponds to our relations to God, and secures happiness.
Objec. 3. The virtues requisite for a state of afflictions, and produced by it, are not wanted to qualify us for a state of happiness.
Ans. Such is not the verdict of experience. Passive submission is essential to right character. Prosperity itself begets extravagant desires; and imagination may produce as much discontent as actual condition. Hence, though we may not need patience in heaven, we shall need that temper which is formed by patience.
Self-love would always coincide with God’s commands, when our interest was rightly understood; but it is liable to error. Therefore, HABITS of resignation are necessary, for all creatures; and the proper discipline for resignation is affliction.
Objec. 4. The trouble and danger of such discipline, might have been avoided by making us at once, what we are intended to become.
Ans. What we are to be, is the effect of what we are to do. God’s natural government is arranged not to save us from trouble or danger, but to enable and incline us to go through them. It is as natural for us to seek means to obtain things, as it is to seek the things; and in worldly things we are left to our choice, whether to improve our powers and so better our condition, or to neglect improvement and so go without the advantage.
Analogy, therefore, makes the same arrangement credible, as to a future state.
III. This state of discipline may be necessary for the display of character
1. Not to the all-knowing Being, but to his creation, or part of it, and in many ways which we know not.
2. It may be a means in disposing of men according to character.
3. And of showing creation that they are so disposed of.
4. Such display of character certainly contributes, largely, to the general course of things considered in this chapter.
CHAPTER VI
OF NECESSITY AS INFLUENCING CONDUCT
Fatalists have no right to object to Christianity, for they of course hold the doctrine to be compatible with what they see in nature.
The question is, whether it be not equally compatible with what Christianity teaches.
To argue on the supposition of so great an absurdity as necessity, is puzzling; and the obscurity and puzzle of the argument must therefore be excused.
I. Necessity does not destroy the proof of an intelligent Author and Governor of the world
1. It does not exclude design and deliberation.
1.) This is matter of actual experience and consciousness.
– Necessity does not account for the existence of any thing, but is only a circumstance relating to its origin. Instance the case of a house: the fatalist admits that it had a builder, and the only question would be, was he obliged to build it as he did?
2.) It is the same as to the construction of the world. To say it exists by necessity must mean it had a maker, who acted by necessity: for necessity is only an abstract notion, and can do nothing.
3.) We say God exists by necessity, because we intuitively discern that there must be an infinite Being, prior to all causes; but we cannot say that every thing so exists. The fact that many changes in nature are produced by man’s contrivance is a proof of this.
4.) Thus though the fatalist does not choose to mean by necessity an agent acting necessarily, he is obliged to mean this.
5.) And it also follows that a thing’s being done by necessity does not exclude design.
2. It does not exclude a belief that we are in a state of religion.
1.) Suppose a fatalist to educate a child on his own principles, – viz.: that he cannot do otherwise than he does; and is not subject to praise or blame. (It might be asked, would he, if possessed of common sense, so educate his child?)
– The child would be delighted with his freedom; but would soon prove a pest, and go to destruction.
– He would meet with checks and rebuffs, which would teach him that he was accountable.
– He would, in the end, be convinced either that his doctrine was wrong, or that he had reasoned inconclusively upon it, and misapplied it.
2.) To apply fatalism to practice, in any other way, would be found equally fallacious: e. g. that he need not take care of his life.
3.) No such absurdity follows the doctrine of freedom.
– Reasoning on this ground is justified by all experience.
– The constitution of things is as if we were free.
4.) If the doctrine of necessity be true, and yet, when we apply it to life, always misleads us; how, then, can we be sure it would not mislead us with respect to future interests?
5.) It follows that if there are proofs of religion on the supposition of freedom, they are just as conclusive on the supposition of necessity.
3. It does not refute the notion that God has a will and a character.
1.) It does not hinder us from having a will and a character; from being cruel, or benevolent, or just, &c.
2.) If necessity be plead as the excuse for crime, it equally excuses the punishment of crime; for if it destroys the sin of the one, it destroys the sin of the other.
3.) The very assumption of injustice in punishing crime, shows that we cannot rid ourselves of the notion of justice and injustice.
Objec. If necessity be reconcilable with the character of God, as portrayed in Christianity, does it not destroy the proof that he has that character; and so destroy the proofs of religion?
Ans. No. Happiness and misery are not our fate, but the results of our conduct. God’s government is that of a father and a magistrate; and his natural rule of government must be veracity and justice. We shall proceed to show that,
II. Necessity does not destroy the proofs of religion
1. It is a plain fact that God rewards and punishes.
1.) He has given us a moral faculty, by which we discern between actions, and approve or disapprove, &c.
2.) This implies a rule, a peculiar kind of rule; i. e. one from which we cannot depart without being self-condemned.
3.) The dictates of our moral faculty are God’s laws, with sanctions. It not only raises a sense of duty, but a sense of security in obeying, and danger in disobeying; and this is an explicit sanction.
4.) God’s government must conform to the nature he has given us; and we must infer that in the upshot happiness will follow virtue, and misery vice.
5.) Hence religious worship is a duty, if only as a means of keeping up the sense of this government.
6.) No objection from necessity can lie against this course of proof.
– The conclusion is wholly and directly from facts; not from what might appear to us to be fit, but from what his actions tell us he wills.
2. Natural religion has external evidence which necessity, if true, does not affect.
1.) Suppose a person convinced of the truths of natural religion, but ignorant of history, and of the present state of mankind, he would inquire:
– How this religion came?
– How far the belief of it extended?
– If he found that some one had totally propounded it, as a deduction of reason, then, though its evidences from reason would not be impaired, its history would furnish no further proof.
2.) But such an one would find, on the contrary,
– That essentially it had been professed in all countries.
– And can be traced up through all ages.
– And was not reasoned out, but revealed.
3.) These things are of great weight.
– Showing natural religion to be conformed to the common sense of mankind.
– And either that it was revealed, or forces itself upon the mind.
– The rude state of the early ages leads to the belief of its being revealed, and such is the opinion of the learned.
3. Early pretences to revelation indicate some original real one from which they were copied.
– The history of revelation is as old as history itself.
– Such a fact is a proof of religion, against which there is no presumption.
– And indicates a revelation prior to the examination of the book said to contain it; and independent of all considerations of its being corrupted, or darkened by fables.
4. It is thus apparent that the external evidence of religion is considerable; and is not affected by the doctrine of necessity.
REMARKS
1. The danger of taking custom, &c. for our moral rule.
1.) We are all liable to prejudice.
2.) Reason may be impaired, perverted, or disregarded.
3.) The matter in hand is of infinite moment.
2. The foregoing observations amount to practical proof.
Objec. Probabilities which cannot be confuted, may be overbalanced by greater probabilities: much more by demonstration. Now, as the doctrine of necessity must be true, it cannot be that God governs us as if we were free when he knows we are not.
Ans. This brings the matter to a point, and the answer is not to be evaded, – viz.: that the whole constitution and course of things shows this reasoning to be false, be the fallacy where it may.
The doctrine of freedom shows where, – viz.: in supposing ourselves necessary agents when in fact we are free.
Admitting the doctrine of necessity, the fallacy evidently lies in denying that necessary agents are accountable; for that they are rewarded and punished is undeniable.
Conclusion. – It follows that necessity, if true, neither proves that God will not make his creatures happy or miserable according to their conduct, nor destroys the proofs that he will do so. That is, necessity, practically, is false.
CHAPTER VII
DIVINE GOVERNMENT A SCHEME IMPERFECTLY COMPREHENDED
Moral government, as a fact, has now been considered; it remains for us to remove objections against its wisdom and goodness. A thing being true does not prove it to be good.
In arguing as to its truth, analogy could only show it to be credible. But, if a moral government be admitted as a fact, analogy makes it credible that it is a scheme or system, and that man’s comprehension of it is necessarily so limited, as to be inadequate to determine its injustice.
This we shall find to be the case.
Doctrine. On the supposition that God exercises moral government, the analogy of nature teaches that it must be a scheme, and one quite beyond our comprehension.
I. The ordering of nature is a scheme; and makes it credible by analogy, that moral government is a scheme
1. The parts curiously correspond to each other; individuals to individuals, species to species, events to events; and all these both immediate and remote.
2. This correspondence embraces all the past, and all the future; including all creatures, actions, and events.
1.) There is no event, which does not depend for its occurrence on some further thing, unknown to us; we cannot give the whole account of any one thing.
2.) Things apparently the most insignificant, seem to be necessary to others, of the greatest importance.
3. If such is God’s natural government, it is credible that such is his moral government.
1.) In fact they are so blended as to make one scheme.
– One is subservient to the other, just as the vegetable kingdom subserves the animal, and our animal organization subserves our mental.
– Every act of God seems to look beyond the occasion, and to have reference to a general plan.
– There is evidently a previous adjustment.
· The periods, &c. for trying men.
· The instruments of justice.
· The kinds of retribution.
2.) The whole comprises a system, a very small part of which is known to us: therefore no objections against any part can be insisted on.
3.) This ignorance is universally acknowledged, except in arguing against religion. That it ought to be a valid answer to objections against religion, we proceed to show.
– Suppose it to be asserted that all evils might have been prevented by repeated interpositions; or that more good might have been so produced; which would be the utmost that could be said: still,
– Our ignorance would vindicate religion from any objections arising from apparent disorders in the world.
– The government of the world might be good, even on those suppositions; for at most they could but suggest that it might be better.
– At any rate, they are mere assertions.
– Instances may be alleged, in things much less out of reach, of suppositions palpably impossible, which all do not see to be so: nor any, at first sight.
4.) It follows that our ignorance is a satisfactory answer to all objections against the divine government.
– An objection against an act of Providence, no way connected with any other thing, as being unjust, could not be answered by our ignorance.
– But when the objection is made against an act related to other and unknown acts, then our ignorance is a full answer.
– Some unknown relation, or unknown impossibility, may render the act not only good, but good in the highest degree.
II. Consider some particular things, in the natural government of God, the like of which we may infer, by analogy, to be contained in his moral government
1. No ends are accomplished without means.
1.) Often, means very disagreeable bring the most desirable results.
2.) How means produce ends, is not learned by reason, but experience.
3.) In many cases, before experience, we should have expected contrary results.
4.) Hence we may infer that those things which are objected against God’s moral government, produce good.
5.) It is evident that our not seeing how the means work good, or their seeming to have an opposite effect, offers no presumption against their fitness to work good.
6.) They may not only be fit, but the only means of ultimate good.
Objec. Though our capacity of vice and misery may promote virtue, and our suffering for sin be better than if we were restrained by force, yet it would have been better if evil had not entered the world.
Ans. It is granted that though sinful acts may produce benefits, to refrain from them would produce more. We have curative pains, yet pain is not better than health.
2. Natural government is carried on by general laws.
1.) Nature shows that this is best: all the good we enjoy is because there are general laws. They enable us to forecast for the procurement of good.
2.) It may not be possible, by general laws, to prevent all irregularities, or remedy them.
3.) Direct interpositions might perhaps remedy many disorders arising under them, but this would have bad effects.
– Encouraging improvidence.
– Leaving us no rule of life.
– Every interposition would have distant effects: so that we could not guess what would be the whole result.
· If it be replied that those distant effects might also be corrected by direct interpositions – this is only talking at random.
Objec. If we are so ignorant as this whole argument supposes, we are too ignorant to understand the proofs of religion.
Ans. 1. Total ignorance of a subject precludes argument, but partial ignorance does not. We may, in various degrees, know a man’s character, and the way he is likely to pursue certain ends; and yet not know how he ought to act to gain those ends. In this case objections to his mode of pursuing ends may be answered by our ignorance, though that he does act in a certain manner is capable of proof. So we may have evidence of God’s character and aims, and yet not be competent judges as to his measures. Our ignorance is a good answer to the difficulties of religion, but no objection to religion itself.
Ans. 2. If our ignorance did invalidate the proofs of religion, as well as the objections, yet is it undeniable that moral obligations remain unaffected by our ignorance of the consequences of obedience or violation. The consequences of vice and virtue may not be fully known, yet it is credible that they may be such as religion declares: and this credibility is an obligation, in point of prudence, to abstain from sin.
Ans. 3. Our answers to the objections against religion, are not equally valid against the proofs of it.
[Answers rehearsed.]
Ans. 4. Our answers, though they may be said to be based on our ignorance, are really not so, but on what analogy teaches concerning our ignorance, – viz.: that it renders us incompetent judges. They are based on experience, and what we do know; so that to credit religion is to trust to experience, and to disregard it is the contrary.
CONCLUSION
1. The reasoning of the last chapter leads us to regard this life as part of a larger plan of things.
1.) Whether we are connected with the distant parts of the universe, is uncertain; but it is very clear we are connected, more or less, with present, past, and future.
2.) We are evidently in the midst of a scheme, not fixed but progressive; and one equally incomprehensible, whether we regard the present, past, or future.
2. This scheme contains as much that is wonderful as religion does: for it certainly would be as wonderful that all nature came into existence without a Creator, as that there should be a Creator: and as wonderful that the Creator should act without any rule or scheme, as that he should act with one; or that he should act by a bad rule, rather than a righteous one.
3. Our very nature compels us to believe that the will and character of the Author of nature, is just and good.
4. Whatever be his character, he formed the world as it is, and controls it as he does, and has assigned us our part and lot.
5. Irrational creatures act their part, and receive their lot, without reflection, but creatures endued with reason, can hardly avoid reflecting whither we go, and what is the scheme, in the midst of which we find ourselves.
[Here follows a recapitulation of the book.]