Читать книгу Social Psychology - Daniel W. Barrett - Страница 128
Representativeness
ОглавлениеIs it true that if it looks like a duck and quacks like a duck, it is a duck? Say your university has a 32-member debate team and a three-member wrestling team. You see Jose, a tall, muscular male student walking across campus dressed in athletic gear, and a friend asks you if Jose is a wrestler or a debater. At first glance and without much thought you respond “wrestler.” Why? Because Jose resembles your image of a stereotypical wrestler, you may immediately assume that he is one. However, upon further reflection, you’d realize that not only is the debate team larger than the wrestling team (which means that he is automatically more likely to debate than to wrestle) but also that debaters come in all shapes and sizes, as do wrestlers. Therefore, the student is much more likely to be a debater than a wrestler—he just happens not to represent your vision of the typical debater. This illustrates the representativeness heuristic, another shortcut that we often rely on to conserve mental resources and make rapid decisions. The representativeness heuristic is used when we categorize a particular instance based on how similar the instance is to a typical member of that category (Kahneman & Frederick, 2002; Tversky & Kahneman, 1974).
In one study, participants were presented with a personality profile of Steve, whose name was randomly pulled out of a set of 100 profiles, 70 of whom were engineers and 30 of whom were librarians. Steve was described as “very shy and withdrawn, invariably helpful, but with little interest in people, or in the world of reality. A meek and tidy soul, he has a need for order and structure, and a passion for detail.” Is Steve an engineer or a librarian? Because Steve resembles the stereotypical librarian, most people would guess librarian. However, in doing so they would be ignoring the base rate probabilities that Steve is one or the other (Jasper & Ortner, 2014; Tversky & Kahneman, 1974). Note that a name randomly pulled out of that set is much more likely to be an engineer, based solely on probabilities. In the Steve example, we fail to take into account the base rate at which the phenomenon occurs.
A second common mistake has to do with the way people appeal to personal anecdotes or limited observation to reject the findings of a particular social psychological study. On many occasions, I have presented research results in class and a student raised his hand and said something to the effect that “I was in a situation like that and I (or someone I know) didn’t act the way the people in the study did, and therefore the study isn’t valid.” For instance, we may be discussing how people tend to affiliate with winning teams—often by donning that team’s shirts and caps—and dissociate from losers (Cialdini et al., 1976), a trend that this is very noticeable after a major sporting event like the Super Bowl or World Cup. A student may say that she wore her Denver Broncos T-shirt the day after they lost to the Seattle Seahawks in the 2014 Super Bowl and consequently conclude that the study is incorrect. However, both she and you need to be cognizant of the fact that social psychology is not able to predict the behavior of any particular person or of every person—nor does it attempt to. Rather, we describe, explain, and predict what most people are likely to think, feel, and do in specific situations. Very rarely—if ever—does each and every one of the participants in a study behave in exactly the same way. Therefore, identifying an apparent exception or counterexample for a given phenomenon and arguing that this disproves the finding represents an overreliance on anecdotal information and a neglect of base rate information.
This base rate fallacy occurs when we ignore underlying probabilities—the base rate or frequency of an event—and instead focus on unusual or atypical instances (Bar-Hillel, 1980). We are particularly likely to do this when we reject the validity of abstract information in favor of concrete, vivid examples, such as anecdotes (Schwarz, Strack, Hilton, & Naderer, 1991; Taylor & Thompson, 1982). In our football example, the fact that most people behave in a specific way (an abstract statement) is not undermined by an instance of one person acting differently (a concrete example). The base rate is how frequent members of various categories occur in the corresponding population (Bar-Hillel, 1990; Kahneman & Tversky, 1972). Given that there are more debaters than wrestlers in the university population, there is a much greater likelihood that Jose is a debater. Likewise, for Steve being an engineer versus librarian.
Relying on the base rate can clearly lead to incorrect decisions. But is it ever useful? Of course it is. We categorize people (and things) for a reason: Categories allow us to simplify our world and make it cognitively manageable. Category members, by definition, share particular traits or characteristics. The traits that make up a category are different from those that make up another category, although some of these characteristics may overlap. Therefore, it is not only natural but also desirable that we use similarity as a basis for categorizing people. The underlying problem with doing so occurs when we ignore other relevant information (like base rates) and use only representativeness (Fiedler, Brinkmann, Betsch, & Wild, 2000).
Representativeness Heuristic: Mental shortcut in which people categorize a particular instance based on how similar the instance is to a typical member of that category
Base Rate Fallacy: Judging how likely an event is to occur, based on unusual or atypical instances, while ignoring its actual base rate or probability of occurrence
Base Rate: Frequency at which a given phenomenon occurs