Читать книгу In Broad Daylight - Gabriele Pedulla - Страница 8
Оглавление1
The Cave and the Mirror
To die, to sleep—to sleep, perchance to dream.
William Shakespeare, Hamlet
Everybody says, “You go to the movies to dream.” That’s a load of crap. In the outskirts, you went to the movies to go to the movies.
Marco Ferreri
In the twentieth century, the auditorium was the true blind spot of film theory. Omnipresent, it remained invisible and unknowable. And yet this blindness coincided only in part with silence about the movie theatre as architectural device. Some critics did ask the question, but then—convinced it had been answered once and for all—hurried on to issues that must have seemed more necessary and urgent: photogenic quality, cinematic language, the relationship of images to physical reality, the power of editing, films’ place in mass culture, the artistic charter of the new discipline . . . The paths they took to incorporate the movie theatre swiftly into reflections on the cinematic apparatus are quite interesting, though; like silences, shortcuts can be instructive—especially in a case like this, where we see a substantial unanimity of vision. It is noteworthy that, here, the main intellectual instrument used to displace the question was the analogy. Instead of beginning with the spectators’ tangible conditions during the film and the way these conditions influence aesthetic reactions, as early as the 1910s film enthusiasts began to ask what a spectator resembled—as if the picture house’s functioning could only be understood through a comparison.
Of the key analogies proposed—essentially two—the first and most famous is that of the cave. In the seventh book of the Republic, Plato had compared the philosopher to a man chained since birth in an underground den. Long convinced that movements projected on the walls of the cavern were the only form of reality, and then having escaped, this man, the story goes, turned back in order to convince his ancient prison companions of the wonders that awaited them outside of the cave, but he received in return only scorn and derision. There are, in fact, some impressive similarities between the cinema experience and Plato’s story, and it is easy to see how the myth immediately became popular among early-twentieth-century film enthusiasts in a society where Latin and Greek classics still constituted a universal cultural reference. The prisoners chained to their seats, the dark, the light at their backs, the silhouettes reproducing the shapes of objects, the wall of the cave where the moving shadows are imprinted; the perfect illusion . . . How to resist the analogy’s charm? How could the idea of men duped, and satisfied, by the pseudo-reality of appearances not remind us of a movie audience (despite the potentially anti-cinematic moral implicit in the Platonic condemnation of any fiction as a copy of a copy, and therefore simply a lie)?
Some probably perceived the risk in presenting spectators as prisoners of a nonexistent world, but the possibility of following Plato must have been too enticing to refuse. In search of a cultural ennobling for cinema, the contributors to film journals of the 1910s and ’20s (the very first to have proposed the image of the cave as an interpretive model for the picture house) had good reason to hope that the classical allusion would offer the newcomer the quarterings of nobility required for admission into the empyrean of the respectable arts. Since then, the danger of providing cinema’s detractors with an argument against it seems to have been of no great concern. On the contrary, the lengthy list of those who, if only in passing, drew on the image of the cave (Edgar Morin, Jean-Louis Baudry, Christian Metz, Vilém Flusser . . .) best confirms the difficulty of doing without the illustrious antecedent. Even Jacques Derrida, in an interview with Cahiers du cinéma in 2001, could not avoid using the same parallel.
Once it was established that the movie theatre reproduced the Platonic cave and that films were able to captivate and deceive spectators with a force of persuasion unknown by any other art, it did not seem necessary to further interrogate the nature, the powers, and the functions of this marvelous engine. All we needed to know about the auditorium was that Plato had in some ways “foreseen” it, not unlike how Leonardo da Vinci had “invented” the tank or the helicopter. In the name of Socrates, Cratylus, and Phaedo, any question could be laid to rest.
It is maybe in part for this reason that the second analogy appeared much later; in its mature form it dates back just to the 1970s, when for the first time—facing the crisis of the traditional circuits—spectators, critics, and directors began to realize that one of the fundamental pieces of the filmic experience as they had known it was disappearing. At the heart of the new theory was the conviction (psychoanalytic in origin, but having taken root enough in common parlance) that this experience is fundamentally like dreaming though we are awake—a condition similar to hypnosis. From here the logic was simple. If going to the movies is equivalent to dreaming, and if indeed there exists a specific relationship between the effects induced by film and by hypnosis (enrapture, the breaking down of barriers, projecting oneself into the picture), the movie theatre cannot help but encourage the spectator’s total relaxation: make him receptive to being kidnapped by the flow of images. The dark, the silence, and the comfortable seats would be all the elements needed to conquer the last resistance of those present, putting them in a state of passivity quite similar to that of a person who sleeps. Exactly as a hypnotic (or psychoanalytical) session has its rituals incorporating metallic pendulums, leather sofas, and commands, to work correctly cinema would also need a precise ceremonial; the auditorium with its darkness, its silence, and its immobility would play a part. The movie palace as gigantic psychoanalytical sofa.
Though the cave analogy remained at a purely intuitive level, its implications never fully developed except by those who used it to revile cinema’s deception outright, the analogy with the dream and hypnosis has a richer history. Less “cultured” (one need not have read Plato, or even Freud, to understand its premises), in the end it offered the only real attempt to explain “scientifically” how viewing conditions influence the spectator during the projection of a film. The credit goes to French critic and novelist Jean-Louis Baudry, who, examining the relationship between dream activity and the cinematic experience, proposed an elaborate theoretical model at the beginning of the 1970s. According to Baudry, who took as his points of departure Lacan’s psychoanalysis and Althusser’s Marxism, cinema’s allure—before that of any single film—lies in the resemblance between the position of the spectator and the mental condition of the infant during the so-called “mirror phase,” when the child produces a first sketch of the idea of “I” while observing his or her own reflection. The physical immaturity of the motor apparatus and the precocious development of the infant’s vision correspond exactly to the experience of the public watching a film. Both are characterized by the dark, the absence of movement, the predominance of viewing over any other activity, the impression that the images are real, and the impossibility of verifying this reality—not to mention the fact that some psychoanalysts describe dreams as images projected on a screen, just as in a film. The desire to relive one’s own infancy with an illusory sense of control over moving pictures would thus be sufficient to explain the twentieth century’s burning passion for the new art. For Baudry, in fact, cinema’s appeal lay entirely in its capacity to transform any audience member into a “transcendental subject,” virtually placed at the center of the universe. From this would stem the medium’s ideological nature—idealizing and potentially conservative—but also its strength and its necessity, if one must read the Platonic myth as a psychic projection of a primitive desire inscribed in the minds of man since the beginning of time.
Baudry’s proposal, taken up by Roland Barthes and Christian Metz, is still quite popular, especially among scholars who include psychoanalysis (not necessarily Lacanian) in their arsenals. Problem solved, then? Absolutely not. Despite the undeniable kinship, there are plenty of reasons to think that neither the cave nor the dream parallel adequately explains what happens in the movie theatre. The problem, of course, is not in the use of analogy; authoritative philosophers have shown that even logic sometimes works through analogic reasoning. However, comparisons can be good or bad, indispensable or completely misleading. Everything depends on their ability to show the similarities of essential elements without being led astray by superficial affinities. And as soon as we look less hastily, the two analogies reveal themselves to be deceitful, that is, built upon dubious consonances.
The American cognitive film theorists—and in particular Noël Carroll—have shown the argumentative fallacies behind the image of the movie theatre as a modern Platonic cave. Unlike the Republic’s prisoners, spectators can always get up and leave, or move their heads; the projected image does not always come from behind the spectators (there is such thing as rear-projection); nothing requires us to read the Platonic myth as the manifestation of an atavistic desire to return to infancy; and so forth. Just as facile, then, is the comparison of a film to dream or hypnosis that is so fundamental to Baudry’s thesis. In this case the list of objections is impressive: even if it is less comfortable, the cinematic apparatus works just as well with spectators who are not seated; movies are not solipsistic like dreams, because anyone can discuss his response with the person next to him; the public is always aware it is in a dark room (an awareness we lose while we sleep); frames are detailed, whereas dream images are often partial and incomplete . . .
Here, too, the list could go on. Yet for our discussion the decisive point is a different one: the extreme confusion about why the movie theatre was made and why people love to see films. The analogies with the cave and the mirror become objectionable first of all because they obscure the particular nature—artistic, or even just recreational—of the cinematic experience. French symbolist Rémy de Gourmont put it well back in 1907, when the idea of the equivalence of film and dream began to spread among the first timid admirers of the new art (Sigmund Freud’s book on the interpretation of dreams, not by chance, had come out in 1900): “The public doesn’t go to the cinema to dream; they go to enjoy themselves.” It would be hard to find a more perfect formula to clear away the relics of the analogies with the cave and the mirror phase. The argument that the pleasure of going to the movies really depends on a desire to regress to infancy lacks validity, too, because in this case it would be necessary to explain how it is therefore possible that people watch films with the same satisfaction on television or on their laptop: that is to say, in radically different conditions than those which Baudry judges essential for the full unfolding of the seductive power of moving images.
What we risk losing with such interpretations is first and foremost the aesthetic function for which the movie house was imagined. When this banal observation—that people go freely to the theatre to take pleasure from moving pictures—is accounted for, the spectator’s resemblance to Plato’s prisoner or Lacan’s infant becomes irrelevant. Let us begin with Plato. How do we ignore the fact that at the movies spectators are not deceived, but rather buy a ticket to attend a show and have a story told to them, just as when they read a novel or go to the playhouse? That we appreciate films not as an alternative to life but as a pause, an intermission, a parenthesis in our daily activities, while Plato’s men are spellbound from the start in a copy of the world which for them constitutes the only reality (“from their childhood,” as specified in the Republic)? That Samuel Taylor Coleridge’s “willing suspension of disbelief,” implicit in every fiction, presupposes a kind of illusion completely different from that experienced by Plato’s men, prisoners of shadows and therefore incapable of seeing the only things that truly exist—namely, ideas?
Not every viewing experience is the same viewing experience, just as not every deception is the same deception—especially if we participate knowingly and willingly. When we consider this simple point, very little remains of the similarities that at the beginning seemed so significant. This is all the truer because the comparison with Plato’s cave seems designed to justify a rejection of cinema for being an instrument of ideological falsification and oppression: an argument against the new medium that was made often throughout the twentieth century, from the right and from the left, by such authoritative figures as Theodor W. Adorno and Georges Duhamel.
The original sin resides in this confusion, and the same could be said of the dream analogy. Cinema is not a machine for taking people back to their childhood through hypnosis, or at least no more than it is a process for distancing them from the direct contemplation of ideas. Just like Lacan’s children, Plato’s prisoners see something, but they do not attend a show in the same way a paying spectator does. And precisely because the Greek philosopher’s preoccupations remain strictly ontological and gnoseological (What is really real? How can I recognize it?), whereas the French psychoanalyst is interested in the process leading the child to acquire the first elements of an adult consciousness (How is the subject born?), every attempt to explain cinema through an analogy with the cave or with the mirror phase enacts an undue slippage. So, we need a new strategy, as we will begin to understand the movie theatre’s function only if we study it as an integral part of the cinematic apparatus: a special device, the equal of the camera or the projector, conceived for giving the spectator a kind of experience different from all others.
Compared to the Platonic myth and the child’s discovery of the subject, the real workings of a movie house in action undoubtedly look less exciting. A few elements suffice: a room, not necessarily big; a white wall or a big screen to project images onto; a series of seats or armchairs (though in old-time theatres people sat on the floor or stood if there were no places left); an opening opposite the screen for light to pass through. Such simple furnishings discouraged additional investigation. And yet, in its minimalism, this structure is the result of a long process of definition led by tradespeople and architects so that the film could work, if not in the best way (as we shall see, in fact, there was not just one), at least in the way that they thought best served their interests—that is to say, to maximize the spectators’ reactions and, in so doing, sell more seats.
The apparent simplicity of the solutions adopted for the movie house might remind us of another twentieth-century aesthetic device: the art gallery. In this case, comparison can be useful. As Brian O’Doherty has recounted, this too is a locale that seems neutral, but whose every detail has been studied in advance so as to obtain the desired effect: to favor the appreciation of the works by a viewer who is always also a potential buyer. So that this can happen—so that the art can “take on its own life”— a gallery must meet a series of extremely precise requirements or risk rapid failure. The size and shape of the spaces, color, lighting, furniture, acoustics: nothing can be left to chance. The fact that the code remains implicit does not mean that its prescriptions—its musts and must nots—are not managed extremely rigorously; on the contrary, as always, the most constricting laws are those of which we are not even aware.
Unlike film historians, though, art historians began long ago to interrogate the conventions of the gallery device, and now we can devise a sort of elementary pentalogy for the aspiring gallery manager, from the shaded windows (to keep the outside world out) and the ceiling lights as the only illumination, to the uniform white of the walls and the parquet flooring or soft moquette (evidently to lend a sense of luxury and comfort that puts the visitor at ease, preparing her for the encounter with beauty), all the way to the imperative of keeping the spaces completely empty, except for the works of art, properly separated so that each can “breathe” (a modest desk at the entrance being the only piece of furniture allowed).
As common and insignificant as they might seem, each of these elements makes its own contribution, at once real and symbolic, to the institution that connoisseurs call simply “the white cube.” This is the official residence of Art: a room without shadows, white, clean, and artificial—ascetic as a clinic and cold as a cenotaph to the unknown soldier. Comfortable but also a tad inhospitable (just enough to make visitors maintain the required respectful attitude), purposely conceived so that the works of art can display themselves in a sort of defensive eternity, removed from time and its vagaries.
From the moment they cross the threshold, visitors must clearly perceive that they have entered a separate space. In the end it is precisely this separation that guarantees the gallery’s efficacy, almost as if the closed space has the power to transform the most banal object into a work of art simply because it is on display there. An aesthetic response will inevitably follow an aesthetic question: this is the first and perhaps principal lesson of Marcel Duchamp’s ready-mades. Urinals, torn posters, shit in a box: anything can be worthy of appreciation when placed in the right context, given that the gallery itself is “art-in-potency” in its purest state.
All of this, naturally, has its price. The gallery not only encourages the aesthetic participation of its visitors, but also, in an anxiety of purity, proclaims its own distance from the outside world, imposing pre-emptive sanctions on any attempt to break down boundaries. Protected from the effects of contact with everyday life, which goes on undisturbed, the white cube resembles a limbo where, while the eyes and the mind are always welcome, the body is barely tolerated, giving rise to a curious Cartesian paradox in which the visitor is and is not there at the same time, entirely absorbed in the contemplation of the work—the only legitimate activity in a space dedicated to this single end.
But the picture house? At first glance, it seems a world away from the white cube. Child of the Boulevard theatre, with its chaotic and noisy public, cinema is the mass art-form of the twentieth century; partly for this reason, the separation of the auditorium from the world outside had been incomplete. No hushed atmosphere, no select clientele, no promise of social climbing. Regular moviegoers had nothing to do with this culture of distinction. Instead there were the couples making out in the dark; the adolescents who skipped school for a matinee and commented on every single scene; the immigrants who needed someone to translate the silent film placards written in a language they did not yet understand and perhaps never would; the workers who took advantage of the venue’s bathroom for their Sunday toilette . . . This is the world that directors have nostalgically depicted since the 1970s: boisterous, lively, multifaceted, even suspect and illegal, but for all of these reasons also absolutely irresistible. Comprehensibly, this intense social life centering on the picture house has conditioned and continues to condition our idea of twentieth-century cinema. In historians’ accounts, the public always appears invested in every activity but paying attention to what is on screen. Instead of watching the audience during the decisive moment—while it views the film—for the most part we see it daydreaming just before the projection begins, or remembering the movie when the show is all over, and often not even that: as soon as the screen lights up, the scholar’s eye turns elsewhere, wanders through the aisles, infiltrates the administrative offices, or escapes to the foyer, in search of new adventures.
Here remains a gap to be filled. Fascinated by moviegoing as an occasion for meeting and socializing, historians have looked at the auditorium as a place where one does everything but watch a film; a place saturated with lives and passions, and precisely for this reason so intriguing; a little microcosm where, almost by chance and as an accessory activity, someone projects a movie. It is not difficult to see why this happened. Focusing on empirical audiences was a way to dismantle the abstractions of Baudry’s, Barthes’s, and Metz’s psychoanalytic models and give space to the plurality of experience that theory seemed to want to erase with a single stroke of its pen; differences existed, and it was necessary to deal with them even at the cost of an abrupt shift toward the social history that would once again obscure the aesthetic problematic. But are we sure that we still ought to talk today of the movie house in the same essentially legendary terms as do Amarcord and The Last Picture Show? The end of the movie theatre epoch and the beginning of a new spectatorial regime make a rethinking of such convictions urgent. If the human heat surrounding that which we might call “the dark cube” or “the opaque cube” (according to a poetic definition by Barthes) has completely monopolized the critics’ attention, generating the equivocation by which the house is studied more as the intersection of histories than as an aesthetic technology or meaning-making machine, it is time to correct this distorted vision, or at least supplement it with a new perspective. We need a Copernican revolution that will refocus the terms of the debate.
In the twentieth century the movie theatre was not a chaotic place of socialization, but a steely modernist device—or rather, it was not one more than the other (even if, as we will see, its origins date back at least four centuries). No less than the art gallery, the auditorium represented an “other” space, carefully distinguished from the world in which we live our normal lives. And just as the white walls and the lights eventually began to seem important to art historians, from now on the auditorium will have to be studied first and foremost as an aesthetic technology designed to encourage the spectator’s concentration.
No one, perhaps, has affirmed the conventional nature of the movie theatre’s protocol as clearly as Peter Greenaway:
Cinema is like an elaborate game with rules. The aim of the game is to successfully suspend disbelief. The audience has been well trained over some eighty years of practice. Necessary circumstances are darkness and a bright projection bulb and a screen. The audience agree to enter a dark space and sit facing in one direction. They will be prepared to sit for some two hours—usually in the evenings.
Greenaway’s comment could be further developed, highlighting, for example, the spectator’s increased willingness to remain immobile in the dark on the weekend, or the often decisive function that the evening show has occupied in the first dates of new couples (cinema as aphrodisiac of the masses?). But what really counts here is the estrangement of the gaze that enables us to observe the cinematic liturgy as something not at all obvious—a social practice that today seems self-evident only because we have been habituated to it since infancy, in this respect truly similar to the experience of Plato’s prisoners. Culture disguised as nature: exactly like the art gallery of immaculate walls and sparkling parquet.
The timelines are not even very far apart. Just like the movie theatre, the gallery, at least in its current form, is a fairly recent institution, more or less the child of impressionism. Only at the end of the nineteenth century did the austere and somewhat aristocratic space we know today emerge, definitively wiping out the eighteenth-century picture galleries with their tendency to amass paintings of very different sizes, periods, artists, subjects, and qualities alongside one other. It is not so strange, then, that the golden age of the “white cube” coincided with the most glorious season of the “dark cube”: from the 1920s until the 1970s, when artists increasingly profaned the gallery’s codes and confines, as everyone began to perceive the entirely conventional nature of the setting. From Yves Klein to Joseph Kosuth, from Christo and Jeanne-Claude to Maurizio Cattelan, a whole current of contemporary art has worked to demystify the exhibition space and its sacred aura.
The coincidence is not without import. Indeed, just as today some propose that we see in the gallery the greatest realization of artistic modernism, we can ask if something similar should not be said with regard to the movie theatre—if, in other words, in the eyes of future generations, it will not be the seats in parallel rows and the oversized screen that were the true core of twentieth-century cinema, far more than directors’ styles, generic conventions, or national schools. Obviously, aesthetic devices like the gallery and the auditorium do not change the works of art they host, but they can influence, even quite profoundly, the visitors’ or viewers’ reactions to them; they impose, in other words, a precise style of viewing and of listening. Reformulated in these terms, even the question of the relationship that exists between La Dolce Vita projected in large format and its video versions viewed at home acquires new interest. While we cannot talk about difference in the terms we do for a print with respect to its original painting, for two editions of the same book, or for two performances of the same song, any notion of perfect identicalness is likewise inapplicable.
The response will always inevitably be twofold: yes, the film on TV is substantially the same as the one we see at the theatre; no, the experience of the film is not identical because different aesthetic devices differently condition our attitude toward the work. As a result, the small screen cannot be treated as simply a downgraded dark cube, almost as if it were merely a question of degree—of better or worse—with respect to an ever-unattainable ideal of the image’s absolute presence.
The need to study the conditions in which a work of art is presented to its public does not obviously only regard moving images. There is an unbridgeable distance between a Francesco Petrarch sonnet read quietly in private and the same sonnet sounded in a theatre by a great actor’s voice, even when not a comma has been altered (never mind the possibility that it might be sung to a Claudio Monteverdi tune); but the same could be said for a play (silent reading, staged reading, dress rehearsal, full production . . .) or for a piece of music, as dancing a waltz by Strauss involves a participation and a pleasure very different from listening to it while relaxing in an armchair. The words of the play text or the notes of a piece of music remain the same, but it would be hard to speak of an identical experience. As Walter Benjamin once wrote, discussing a similar problem, “the power of a text is different when it is read from when it is copied out . . . because the reader follows the movement of his mind in the free flight of daydreaming, whereas the copier submits it to command.”
However, it is with moving images that such an approach proves particularly fruitful, due to the contrast between the fixity of an infinitely reproducible work and the multiplicity of responses to it (which are connected to its presentation). To speak of viewing and listening styles thus means forgetting the sterile contraposition of good sense—which says that a film on the small screen should not be fundamentally different from the same film seen at the theatre—with the certainty, not just of the most demanding cinephiles, that between the two experiences an irreducible distance nonetheless remains.
This is not the only reason that today we need a unitary history of distinct aesthetic devices, from the playhouse and the picture palace to television and individual media. The concept of viewing style—fundamental to this unitary history—also helps explain why the effects of the movie theatre’s crisis appeared so belatedly. The canonical date of the landing of films in American homes is usually set at 1956, when the Hollywood majors closed the first important contract with the national networks ceding broadcast rights for black-and-white films produced before 1948. It could have been a revolution; instead, from that moment on the spilling over of the most successful films from the big to the small screen produced no decisive change in the audience’s behavior. For a generation or two, the theatre remained the only “normal” way to see a movie. Those who stayed at home tried to re-create the viewing conditions a picture house would have guaranteed. Lights were turned out; armchairs were placed at the right distance; someone unplugged the telephone so as not to be interrupted—during what represented a still rather exceptional event, given the limited number of showings and broadcast hours of the early years. We will have a chance to return to this problem, but what is important here is that the cinematic viewing model was so strong as to be exported even in the absence of some of the elements most characteristic of the movie theatre.
Today this relationship has been turned on its head. At just over a century since the construction of the first buildings designed to host the Lumière brothers’ invention, what seems to have entered into crisis once and for all is the particular viewing style encouraged by the auditorium but so prestigious and pervasive as to be adopted elsewhere, when spectators have to resign themselves and attend a film without all of the comforts of a panoramic screen or a perfectly darkened room. If in the 1950s and ’60s (but later, too) men and women watching a movie continued to behave as if they were at a picture house, regardless of the viewing conditions, today the opposite seems to be true: the movie theatre is the anomaly—the infraction of a norm and an aesthetic practice that find their codification in the domestic space.
But let us avoid any misunderstandings. To say that the age of the movie theatre is coming to an end is much different from prophesying its complete disappearance—an event that seems neither imminent nor even probable. Simply put, while the auditorium incarnated the optimal filmic experience, since at least the 1970s the monopoly of the cinematic viewing style has entered, little by little, into crisis. The picture house was first surrounded by television and then by multiple supports in competition among themselves, to such an extent that none of them can hope for the exclusivity that the movie theatres once had. In light of this phenomenon, the fact that for some years the number of venues and the volume of box office takings (but not the number of spectators) has started to grow again in the Western world is in the end an irrelevant detail. It took a few post-cinematic generations for television to escape once and for all from the tutelage of its older brother—cinema. Only in the final quarter of the last century did the new arrival enter maturity and truly begin to assert its autonomy. Actually, the process is ongoing, but the signals of an acceleration multiply, and with the fall of the movie theatre as a viewing paradigm, soon nothing will be as it was before.
The auditorium’s slow decline brings with it the irreversible decay of one model of spectatorship; and, in a chain reaction, the disappearance of this spectator—which we might call “classical”—produces a radically selective memory of bygone cinema. We have all had the painful experience of discovering those films revered in our memories that on the small screen just do not “cut it.” Since all of the reinforcements concocted for movies disappear at home, we are no longer surprised that so few films really hold up to the video test; and yet, with the exception of Serge Daney, few critics have explored the effects of cinema’s forced domestication. On video, dark photography becomes indecipherable; crowd scenes lose any epic power; the spatial composition of panoramic formats like cinemascope is completely distorted. Never mind the stylistic choices whose meanings change when they pass from the big to the small screen, like the close-up, which today—after all the abuses of the shot/reverse shot on television—is difficult to still define as the “soul of cinema,” as Jean Epstein did in the 1920s: a sort of explosion in the continuity of a film, a wrinkling of the story, where the camera’s approach to objects was never gratuitous, but indicated a discovery, an emotional climax, an epiphany. There is no doubt that in the years to come the rethinking of the canon will be determined partly by old films’ differing ability to adapt to the new medium.
Twentieth-century directors conceived of their films imagining them projected under very precise conditions; those conditions having disappeared, these works will suffer from the demise of the device for which they were originally envisioned. Every art continuously creates and recreates its past; but when it comes to cinema, the big screen’s crisis not only accelerates this process, but also reshapes our appreciation of each movie. We need to think of twentieth-century cinema as an animal in an ecosystem; cast out of that ecosystem, films must either adapt to the new environment, survive in little protective enclaves (cineforums and national cinemathèques), or simply die out. But surely, for all of them, natural selection is already underway with a violence that is unprecedented, perhaps excluding only the passage from silent films to the talkies—when it became normal for movies to “speak,” and those that did not were quickly condemned to oblivion.
Even if today only a tiny portion of moving images are consumed according to the rigorous behavioral code that characterizes the dark cube, that device was the secret engine of twentieth-century cinema. And yet, precisely because we prepare to leave that season behind, it is far more certain that, without the movie theatre as we knew it, film history would be completely different—just as the movies of the past have begun to seem different, very different, since the small screen has begun to erode the auditorium’s centrality. Despite appearances, the cinematic viewing style’s decline has relatively little to do with our past—nostalgia for the lost Saturday night or Sunday afternoon movie ritual, the mournful cries of cinephiles for every old theatre reopened as a gym or mall, the establishment of an enduring canon. Rather, to think about the movie theatre today is to ask very precise questions about the future of moving images. While competition from television by now seems an ancient phenomenon requiring no further analysis, the change we are witnessing is something without precedent, and relates to the spectator’s comprehensive attitude toward moving pictures—wherever they are.
This story coming to a close, another immediately opens up. Because the movie theatre has such a profound impact on directors’ works and styles, it would certainly be surprising if its eclipse and the consequent transition from the age of cinematography to that of individual media (the disc player, the computer, the videophone . . .) did not bring with them major repercussions. This is our present, and to reconstruct the vicissitudes of the dark cube in its first century of life means principally to investigate this epochal metamorphosis just as it is happening.