Читать книгу Care in Technology - Xavier Guchet - Страница 11

I.2. The two-layered model of care

Оглавление

That there is a close link between, on the one hand, the fact that the human is a living being – which makes it dependent on various conditions to meet its vital needs – and, on the other hand, the fact that it has an essential relationship to the care applied to the maintenance and provision of these conditions, has been widely stressed by the ethics of care8. This link is highlighted, incidentally, in a fable which comes to us from a Latin author named Hygin, which Heidegger relates in paragraph 42 of Being and Time (Heidegger 1962, p. 242):

Once when ‘Concern’ [who is also care, Cura] was crossing a river, she saw some clay: she thoughtfully took up a piece and began to shape it. While she was meditating on what she had made, Jupiter (Jovis) came by. ‘Concern’ asked him to give it spirit, and this he gladly granted. But when she wanted her name to be bestowed upon it, he forbade this, and demanded that it be given his name instead. While ‘Concern’ and Jupiter were disputing, Earth (Tellus) arose and desired that her own name be conferred on the creature, since she had furnished it with part of her body. They asked Saturn [that is, Time] to be their arbiter, and he made the following decision, which seemed a just one: ‘Since you, Jupiter, have given its spirit, you shall receive that spirit at its death; and since you, Earth, have given its body, you shall receive its body. But since ‘Concern’ first shaped this creature, she shall possess it as long as it lives. And because there is now a dispute among you as to its name, let it be called homo, for it is made out of humus (earth).

Commenting briefly on this fable, Heidegger notes that Concern or Care is not envisaged only as that to which the human Dasein remains committed during its entire life and as that which constitutes it, but that “this priority of ‘care’ emerges in connection with the familiar way of taking man as compounded of body (earth) and spirit” (Heidegger 1962, p. 243).

The meaning of the fable is that the human being will only be a composite of body and spirit at its death, and at this time only can the sharing between Jovis and Tellus be made; before this, what defines the human is the fact that it lives, that it is a living being. As a living being, the human is one, not split, care being precisely that which prevents the split between its natural and not-natural parts. Care, in terms of the human being, means above all else refusing any form of split between the body and the spirit: there is not, on one side, care in the sense of purely technological caregiving, with an objectivized body as its area of intervention; and on the other side care in the sense of taking care, attentive to the human being as spirit and free will. Care cannot be two cares, it is a unity or nothing at all9.

This requirement of unity in care, an indivisibility of caregiving and taking care, has been particularly pronounced in the field of medical ethics, except however that these two aspects of care, although not separate, are not so much merged into a truly unitary care. There are two layers of care and they are clearly hierarchical. It has in effect become a commonplace to recall that the therapeutic act in the technical sense of the term, that is to say caregiving (cure), is devoid of any moral value if it is not inserted into a more essential relationship of care which envelopes it. The greatest risk is that, while thus conceived according to a two-layer model, care becomes precisely two quite distinct and unrelated cares – and even worse, that care within the meaning of caregiving will eventually prevail over care within the meaning of taking care. As psychoanalyst Donald W. Winnicott deplored at the beginning of the 1970s, “Cure, in the sense of remedy, successful eradication of disease and its cause, tends today to overlay cure as care” (Winnicott 2017, p. 192). However, as stressed by the preface writers of an Italian collective work (Donghi and Preta 1995), the risk of splitting care and giving priority, as Winnicott deplored, to cure as remedy over care, results specifically in an inability to properly pose the problem of the relationships between body and spirit, and their unity. In other words, a relationship of reciprocal implication is forged here between, on one hand, the conception of the human as a living being – but in the sense of a being composed of body and spirit unified by care – and on the other hand, a two-layer conception of care.

However, this two-layer conception of care, well documented in the field of medical ethics, does not confine itself there: it is also found in the invocation of care for nature and it leads to a blurring of its meaning. Not, incidentally, that any idea of care for nature should invariably find its only possible model in medical care (Pierron 2019). Thus, van Rensselaer Potter, one of the theoreticians of the concept of bioethics, considered that medical bioethics, far from being possibly the basis for a global concept of care by extension of the care due to humans to the care due to nature, was on the contrary only a shrinkage of a broader concept of bioethics, linking human health and health of the environment (Gaille 2013). That being said, the need to establish a hierarchical relationship between cure and care now extends to the whole set of activities where care is required. The penetration of the ethics of care into environmental ethics illustrates this phenomenon of extension: we are required not only to interact in a prudent and careful manner with nature, but also to assume that these interactions are of a moral scope and that, therefore, we are morally obliged to comply with the values of prudence and fair measure.

In its most general sense, the idea of care for nature therefore points towards the same two-layer conception of care as that of medical ethics. It is still a matter, here as there, of conceiving care as a single care; however, this care does indeed have two layers in a hierarchical relationship. On the one hand, there is the properly technical level of care, which is the care that we must take of natural things if we are to succeed in our undertakings, in order to avoid the misfortunes of the man of Song. Mengzi, a Chinese philosopher of the 4th century B.C.E., a follower of Confucian thought, tells us that “a man of Song10, distressed to not see his plants growing fast enough, had the idea of pulling on them from above. Returning home in haste, he said to his people: “I am tired today, I have been helping the corn to grow long” (Mencius, 1970, p. 190). On hearing this, his son rushed to go to see, but the shoots had already dried. Here is an unwise technical act, harmful due to lack of attention and care brought to the specific needs of the plants; but there is also, on the other hand, the moral layer of care, which must provide technical acts of care with their guiding values. The two-layer conception of care extends to nature particularly when it is assigned an intrinsic and not only instrumental value11: moral respect for nature must regulate the technical acts that are deployed.

Care in Technology

Подняться наверх