Читать книгу Set Theory And Foundations Of Mathematics: An Introduction To Mathematical Logic - Volume I: Set Theory - Douglas Cenzer - Страница 10

2.1. The Algebra of Sets

Оглавление

In naive set theory, there is a universe U of all elements. For example, this may be the set of real numbers or the set = {0, 1, 2, . . . } of natural numbers, or perhaps some finite set. The fundamental relation of set theory is that of membership. For a subset A of U and an element a of A, we write aA to mean that a belongs to A, or is an element of A. The family (U) of subsets of U has the natural Boolean operations of union, intersection, and complement, as follows.

Definition 2.1.1. For any element a of U and any subsets A and B of U,

(1) aAB if and only if aAaB;

(2) aAB if and only if aAaB;

(3) aA if and only if ¬ aA.

Here we use the symbols ∨, ∧, and ¬ to denote the logical connectives or, and, and not. We will frequently write xA as an abbreviation for ¬ xA.

The convention is that two sets A and B are equal if they contain the same elements, that is


This is codified in the Axiom of Extensionality, one of the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory which will be presented in detail in Chapter 3. The family of subsets of U composes a Boolean algebra, that is, it satisfies certain properties such as the associative, commutative, and distributive laws. We will consider some of these now, and leave others to the exercises. We will put in all of the details at first, and later on leave some of them to the reader.

Proposition 2.1.2 (Commutative Laws). For any sets A and B,

(1) AB = BA;

(2) AB = BA.

Proof. (1) Let x be an arbitrary element of U. We want to show that, for any xU, xAB xBA. By propositional logic, this means we need to show that xABxBA and that xBAxAB. To prove the first implication, we need to suppose that xAB and then deduce that xBA. We now proceed as follows. Suppose that xAB. Then by Definition 2.1.1, xA or xB. It follows by propositional logic that xBxA. Hence by Definition 2.1.1, xBA. Thus we have shown xABxBA. A similar argument shows that xBAxAB. Then xAB xBA. Since x was arbitrary, we have (∀x)[xAB xBA]. It then follows by Extensionality that AB = BA.

Part (2) is left to the exercises.


The notion of subset, or inclusion, is fundamental.

Definition 2.1.3. For any sets A and B, we have the following conditions:

(1) AB (∀x)[xAxB]. We say that A is included in B if AB.

(2) AB ABAB.

Proposition 2.1.4 (Associative Laws).

(1) A ∩ (BC) = (AB) ∩ C;

(2) A ∪ (BC) = (AB) ∪ C.

Proof. (1) A ∩ (BC) = (AB) ∩ C. Let x be an arbitrary element of U and suppose that xA ∩ (BC). Then by Definition 2.1.1, we have xA and xBC and therefore xB and xC. It follows by propositional logic that xAxB, and thus xAB. Then by propositional logic, (xAB) ∧ xC. Thus by Definition 2.1.1, x ∈ (AB) ∩ C. Thus xA ∩ (BC) → x ∈ (AB) ∩ C. A similar argument shows that x ∈ (AB) ∩ Cx ∈ (A ∩ (BC)). Since x was arbitrary, we have (∀x)[xA ∩ (BC) → x ∈ (AB) ∩ C]. It now follows by Extensionality that A ∩ (BC) = (AB) ∩ C.

Part (2) is left to the exercises.


The following proposition can help simplify a proof that two sets are equal.

Proposition 2.1.5. For any sets A and B, A = B ABBA.

Proof. Suppose first that A = B. This means that (∀x)[xA xB]. Now let xU be arbitrary. Then xA xB. It follows from propositional logic that xAxB and also xBxA. Since x was arbitrary we have (∀x)[xAxB] and (∀x)[xBxA]. Then by Definition 2.1.3, it follows that AB and BA.

Next suppose that AB and BA. The steps above can be reversed to deduce that A = B.


The empty set is defined by the following property:


It is easy to see that = U and that = U. This is left as an exercise.

Proposition 2.1.6 (DeMorgan’s Laws). For any sets A and B,

(1) (AB) = AB;

(2) (AB) = AB.

Proof. (1) We will prove this by a sequence of equivalent statements. Let xU be arbitrary. Then x ∈ (AB) if and only if xAB if and only if ¬(xAxB) if and only if xAxB if and only if xAxB if and only if xAB.

Part (2) is left to the exercises.


The universal set U and the empty set are the identities of the Boolean algebra (U). This is spelled out in the following proposition.

Proposition 2.1.7 (Identity Laws). For any set A,

(1) AA = U;

(2) AA = .

Proof. (1) One inclusion follows from the fact that BU for all sets B. For the other inclusion, let xU be arbitrary. It follows from propositional logic (the so-called law of excluded middle) that xA ∨ ¬xA. Then by Definition 2.1.1, xAxA and then xAA. Thus UAA.

(2) This follows from (1) using DeMorgan’s laws. Given part (1) that AA = U, we obtain = U = (AA) = A ∩ (A) = AA = AA.


The inclusion relation may be seen to be a partial ordering. We have just seen above that it is antisymmetric, that is AB and BA imply A = B. Certainly this relation is reflexive, that is, AA. Transitivity is left to the exercises.

Inclusion may be defined from the Boolean operations in several ways.

Proposition 2.1.8. The following conditions are equivalent:

(1) AB;

(2) AB = A;

(3) AB = B.

Proof. We will show that (1) and (2) are equivalent and leave the other equivalence to the exercises.

(1) (2): Assume that AB. Let x be arbitrary. Then xAxB. Now suppose that xA. Then xB and hence xAxB, so that xAB. Thus AAB. Next suppose that xAB. Then xAxB, so certainly xA. Thus ABA. It follows that AB = A, as desired.

(2) (1): Suppose that AB = A. Let x be arbitrary and suppose that xA. Since AB = A, it follows that xAB. That is, xAxB, so that xB. Hence AB.


We will sometimes write A \ B for AB. The proof of the following is left as an exercise.

Proposition 2.1.9. The following conditions are equivalent:

(1) AB;

(2) BA;

(3) A \ B = .

There are some interactions between the inclusion relation and the Boolean operations, in the same way that inequality for numbers interacts with the addition and multiplication operations.

Proposition 2.1.10. For any sets A, B, and C, we have the following properties:

(1) If BA and CA, then BCA.

(2) If AB and AC, then ABC.

Proof. (1) Assume that BA and CA. Let x be arbitrary and suppose that xBC. This means that xBxC. There are two cases. Suppose first that xB. Since BA, it follows that xA. Suppose next that xC. Since CA, it follows again that xA. Hence xBCxA. Since x was arbitrary, we have BCA, as desired.

The proof of part (2) is left to the exercises.


Exercises for Section 2.1

Exercise 2.1.1. Prove the Commutative Law for intersection, that is, for any sets A and B, AB = BA.

Exercise 2.1.2. Prove the Associative Law for union, that is, for any sets A, B, and C, A ∪ (BC) = (AB) ∪ C.

Exercise 2.1.3. Prove the Distributive Laws, that is, for any sets A, B, and C, A ∪ (BC) = (AB) ∩ (AC) and A ∩ (BC) = (AB) ∪ (AC).

Exercise 2.1.4. Show that, for any set A, ⊆ A and AU.

Exercise 2.1.5. Show that, for any set A, (A) = A.

Exercise 2.1.6. Show that, for any set A, A ∪ = A and AU = A.

Exercise 2.1.7. Show that, for any set A, A ∩ = and AU = U.

Exercise 2.1.8. Complete the argument that the relation ⊆ is a partial ordering by showing that it is transitive, that is, if AB and BC then AC.

Exercise 2.1.9. Show that, for any sets A and B, AB if and only if AB = B.

Exercise 2.1.10. Show that the following conditions are equivalent:

(1) AB;

(2) BA;

(3) A \ B = .

Exercise 2.1.11. Show that, for any sets A, B, and C, AB and AC imply that ABC.

Set Theory And Foundations Of Mathematics: An Introduction To Mathematical Logic - Volume I: Set Theory

Подняться наверх