Читать книгу Politics and Scepticism in La Mothe Le Vayer - Ioana Manea - Страница 5

Introduction

Оглавление

The “Plutarch of [his] century”, whose works, in a “prodigious number” (“d’un nombre prodigieux”), were “in everyone’s hands” (“dans les mains de tout le monde”),1 La Mothe Le Vayer possessed great learning, which in addition to underlying a prolific literary career, gave him access to the most exclusive power circles of his time. Born in a family belonging to the noblesse de robe, he inherited the office of assistant attorney-general of the Paris Parliament, which he nevertheless abandoned in order to dedicate himself to writing. Besides the place within the French Academy (1639), his books also earned him other offices. He was the tutor of the Duc d’Anjou, the younger brother of Louis XIV, who would later become the Duc d’Orléans. In addition he was the tutor of the future Louis XIV himself, albeit for a shorter period. He also held the office of State Councillor.2 While being generally acknowledged, the learning that nourished his books and made his great reputation did not always meet unanimous praise. For instance, according to Vigneul-Marville, La Mothe Le Vayer’s writings are “centos” (“rhapsodies”) that “are no longer to our taste” (“ne sont plus de notre goût”), since they can be reduced to “an accumulation of everything that he has found best throughout his readings” (“un amas de ce qu’il avait trouvé de meilleur dans le cours de ses lectures”).3 Vigneul-Marville voices the opinion of the mondains of the time who, while advocating a literature in the French language, disapproved of the “rhetoric of quotations” (“rhétorique des citations”) 4 to which adhered La Mothe Le Vayer, in keeping with the humanist tradition.

Whether appreciated or considered out of fashion, La Mothe Le Vayer was certainly a writer who enjoyed a great reputation à la Cour et à la ville.5 The rich erudition on which were based his numerous works represented the material that allowed him to defend a Pyrrhonism that found its acme in the Dialogues faits à l’imitation des Anciens which, according to Bayle, contained “a lot of libertinism” (“beaucoup de libertinage”),6 a term that following Furetière’s Dictionnaire universel referred to an irreverent attitude towards religion or ethics. Unlike the Dialogues faits à l’imitation des Anciens, the treatise De l’Instruction de Monseigneur le Dauphin drew Bayle’s attention because of its quality. Indeed, the work on the education of the prince was considered by the author of the Dictionnaire historique et critique as one of the best that La Mothe Le Vayer ever wrote.7

Bayle’s high opinion of the treatise addressed by La Mothe Le Vayer to the Dauphin seems to confirm, among others, its relative success in Italy. Indeed, in 1647, seven years after its publication in France, De l’Instruction de Monseigneur le Dauphin was published in Venice, under the title of Istruttione de’ Prencipi. Furthermore, the seven treatises written for the prince by La Mothe Le Vayer between 1651 and 1658 were published several times under the title of Scuola de’ Prencipi, e de’ Cavalieri, twice in Bologna, in 1676 and 1677, and seven times in Venice between 1677 and 1737. As it results from the article by Lorenzo Bianchi, in his letter to the readers, the translator of Scuola de’ Prencipi, e de’ Cavalieri explained his translation as an attempt to make La Mothe Le Vayer’s didactic work accessible to a wider public, which did not include only princes.8

Unlike the 17th century readers, recent scholarship usually mentions the treatises that La Mothe Le Vayer wrote for the education of the future king in order to point out the duplicity that seems to lie at the core of his work. In so doing, the scholars rely on what they consider to be the contradiction between the books for the prince, which are obviously written in an attempt to collaborate with the powerful and the Dialogues faits à l’imitation des Anciens, which are said to be targeted at any type of political power and especially at the monarchical absolutism from the France of the time. This dual interpretation finds its sharpest expression in the founding study of René Pintard, Le Libertinage érudit dans la première moitié du XVIIe siècle. In the view of Pintard, La Mothe Le Vayer betrays several times the philosophical ideal of the intellectual freedom and rest (“repos”), which is defended by Orontes, his spokesperson in the Dialogues faits à l’imitation des Anciens. One of these times is when publishing the treatises for the future king, since “in a sense the dogmatic Politique du Prince will disown the Pyrrhonian politics of Orasius Tubero” (“en un sens la dogmatique Politique du Prince reniera la pyrrhonienne politique d’Orasius Tubero”).9 Going beyond the ethical judgements, Jean-Pierre Cavaillé argues that La Mothe Le Vayer’s career as a tutor – and, implicitly, we can add, the treatises that he wrote when holding or trying to reach this office – prevented the scholars from “paying attention to Le Vayer’s boldness in the Dialogue traitant de la politique sceptiquement” (“prêter attention aux audaces de Le Vayer dans le Dialogue traitant de la politique sceptiquement”).10 Enlarging on Cavaillé’s thesis of a La Mothe Le Vayer who dissimulates his aim of undermining power, Sophie Gouverneur argues against his “schizophrenia” (“schizophrénie”) and holds that he develops a “prudence”, which “far from amounting to a hypocritical attitude” (“loin de se réduire chez lui à une attitude hypocrite”), enables him, among other things, to “communicate subversive thoughts in the field of politics and ethics” (“communiquer des pensées subversives en matière de politique comme de morale”).11

The scholars’ broad defence of the idea that La Mothe Le Vayer aims at the “devaluation of politics, but in fact especially of the men in power and of those who pride themselves on the science of power” (“dépréciation de la politique, mais en fait d’abord des hommes de pouvoir, et de ceux qui prétendent à la science du pouvoir”),12 has mostly resulted in an emphasis on the study of the Dialogues faits à l’imitation des Anciens, perceived as the climax of a libertinism and a decrease in the interest for the treatises written for the education of the prince. For instance, placing them in the context of a moment of “golden servitude” (“servitude dorée”), which alternates with the moments of “philosophical freedom” (“liberté philosophique”), Pintard describes the seven treatises written by La Mothe Le Vayer for the prince between 1651 and 1658 as “dogmatic works, of a dogmatism of circumstance” (“œuvres dogmatiques, d’un dogmatisme de circonstance ”).13 Building on the idea of the clear separation between the private and the public spaces, associated either with the freedom of thought, or with the exterior submission to authority, Françoise Charles-Daubert considers that La Politique du Prince, one of the works that belongs to the series mentioned above, is a “school account, essentially inspired by Aristotle and, broadly considering everything, quite less original” (“exposé scolaire, essentiellement inspiré d’Aristote et à tout prendre bien peu original”).14

The idea of the sharp division between what is being said in private and in public has recently been challenged mostly because La Mothe Le Vayer chose to publish his works.15 Despite agreeing with previous scholarship on the fact that, when writing for the prince, La Mothe Le Vayer argues for “moderation” against “excess”, Gouverneur holds that, in fact, he aims to become involved in the political field in a “much more global and radical manner, through the libertine use of scepticism and the aesthetics of prudence” (“de manière bien plus globale et radicale, par l’usage libertin du scepticisme et de l’esthétique prudentielle”).16 Following this remark, it would have certainly been interesting to see what is the form taken by the aspiration for a complete action in the political field in the treatises for the future king, which are obviously privileged instruments for acting on politics. Nevertheless, when studying La Mothe Le Vayer’s works of princely education, Gouverneur seems to focus more on topics that are either related to the traditional knowledge that the king is supposed to acquire and that concerns its hierarchical structure, or to a certain moderation that concerns the limitation of the abuses to which the reason of State is likely to open the way.17 Although he is not interested in taking part in the political action, La Mothe Le Vayer, as perceived by Cavaillé, needs the “show” (“spectacle”) offered by politics in order to practise his “strength” (“fermeté”) and “singularity” (“singularité”) through the profit he makes of looking critically at it.18 Yet the idea of the critical look at a power that tolerates opposition as long as it is expressed through “dis/simulation”19 may have gained deeper insights into La Mothe Le Vayer’s elusive thought through the analysis of the relationship between dissidence and the teaching books for the Dauphin, which needless to say had a special connection with political authority.

Despite being questioned, as we have already seen, the distinction between what is meant by La Mothe Le Vayer for the two spheres, the public and the private, still influences the attention enjoyed by the books that he wrote in order to support or, apparently, to undermine the powerful. In studying this dichotomy that seems to be more alleged than actually studied, my book will deal with the apparent ambivalence of the intellectual La Mothe Le Vayer, who built his career on writing at the same time for and against power. Therefore, my study will not only examine the books that he is said to have written against the powerful, but also those that he wrote for the powerful. The element that will underlie my approach to his works will be scepticism, which La Mothe Le Vayer acknowledges as his distinctive feature as a writer. For this purpose, my first chapter studies, on the one hand, his relationship to the two sceptical traditions inherited from Antiquity, Pyrrhonism and the New Academy and, on the other hand, the influence exerted by scepticism on his writing, his view of the world and the explanation it was given by science, which at the time was making great progress. The following chapter will go more thoroughly into the analysis of scepticism, by analysing what is usually considered to be its subversive role in the works by La Mothe Le Vayer that seem to aim at weakening the political regime and its representatives. As a counterpart to the chapter dealing with the works that apparently sap the power, the third chapter is about the treatises that La Mothe Le Vayer wrote in order to serve the power and especially in order to educate the prince. In so doing, this chapter will focus on bringing out the knowledge that the author aimed to transmit to the king about concepts like the reason of State, which were highly debated by the political literature of the moment.

After having examined La Mothe Le Vayer’s apparently ambivalent argumentation on power, the book ends with a chapter built around a question that is still relevant nowadays: should an intellectual who perceives the shortcomings of the politicians and of the regime they represent withdraw from public life or be actively involved in it in order to contribute to the diminishing of its faulty aspects? In order to answer this question, my research will compare the two apparently contradictory types of texts written by La Mothe Le Vayer by relying on concepts like intertextuality,20 which makes possible the analysis of the elements that are common to several texts. Further, the aspects revealed by the comparison between the two types of works will be studied from the perspective of prudence, which was a key-concept in the political treatises of the time. Concepts belonging to fields like literary studies, political or moral philosophy will be used for bringing out the attitude towards the involvement in politics of the two-faced philosopher that La Mothe Le Vayer seems to be at first glance.

Politics and Scepticism in La Mothe Le Vayer

Подняться наверх