Читать книгу Silence - John Cage - Страница 15
ОглавлениеCOMPOSITION AS PROCESS
The following three lectures were given at Darmstadt (Germany) in September 1958. The third one, with certain revisions, is a lecture given earlier that year at Rutgers University in New Jersey, an excerpt from which was published in the Village Voice, New York City, in April 1958.
I. Changes
Having been asked by Dr. Wolfgang Steinecke, Director of the Internationale Ferienkurse für Neue Musik at Darmstadt, to discuss in particular my Music of Changes, I decided to make a lecture within the time length of the Music of Changes (each line of the text whether speech or silence requiring one second for its performance), so that whenever I would stop speaking, the corresponding part of the Music of Changes itself would be played. The music is not superimposed on the speech but is heard only in the interruptions of the speech—which, like the lengths of the paragraphs themselves, were the result of chance operations.
Note to ebook reader: what may appear to be missing lines in this section are intentional.
This is a lec-
ture on changes
that have taken
place in my com-
position means,
with particu-
lar reference
to what, a dec-
ade ago, I
termed “structure” and
“method.” By “struc-
ture” was meant the
division of
a whole into
parts; by “method,”
the note-to-note
procedure. Both
structure and meth-
od (and also
“material”—
the sounds and si-
lences of a
composition)
were, it seemed to
me then, the prop-
er concern of
the mind (as op-
posed to the heart)
(one’s ideas
of order as
opposed to one’s
spontaneous
actions); whereas
the two last
of these, namely
method and ma-
terial, to-
gether with form
(the morpholo-
gy of a con-
tinuity)
were equally
the proper con-
cern of the heart.
Composition,
then, I viewed, ten
years ago, as
an activity integrat-
ing the oppo-
sites, the ration-
al and the ir-
rational, bring-
ing about, i-
deally, a
freely moving
continui-
ty within a
strict division
of parts, the sounds,
their combina-
tion and succes-
sion being ei-
ther logical-
ly related
or arbitrar-
ily chosen.
¶The strict divi-
sion of parts, the
structure, was a
function of the
duration as-
pect of sound, since,
of all the as-
pects of sound in-
cluding frequen-
cy, amplitude,
and timbre, dur-
ation, alone,
was also a
characteris-
tic of silence.
The structure, then,
was a divi-
sion of actu-
al time by con-
ventional met-
rical means, me-
ter taken as
simply the meas-
urement of quan-
tity. ¶In the
case of the So-natas and In-terludes (which I finished in nine- teen forty-eight), only structure was organized, quite roughly for the work as a whole, exactly, however, with- in each single piece. The method was that of con- sidered impro- visation (main- ly at the pi- ano, though i- deas came to me at some mo- ments away from the instrument.
The materi-
als, the pia-
no prepara-
tions, were chosen
as one chooses
shells while walking
along a beach.
The form was as
natural as
my taste permit-
ted: so that where,
as in all of
the Sonatas and two of the Interludes, parts were to be re- peated, the for- mal concern was to make the prog- ress from the end of a section to its begin- ning seem inev- itable. ¶The structure of one of the Sona-tas, the fourth, was one hundred meas- ures of two-two time, divided into ten u- nits of ten meas- ures each. These u- nits were combined in the propor- tion three, three, two, two, to give the piece large parts, and they were subdi- vided in the same proportion to give small parts to each unit. In contrast to a structure based on the frequen- cy aspect of sound, tonali- ty, that is, this rhythmic structure was as hospi- table to non- musical sounds, noises, as it was to those of the convention- al scales and in- struments. For noth- ing about the structure was de- termined by the materials which were to oc- cur in it; it was conceived, in fact, so that it could be as well expressed by the absence of these materials as by their pres- ence. ¶In terms of the oppo- sition of free- dom and law, a piece written ten years before the Sonatas andInterludes, Con-struction in Met-al, presents the same relation- ship, but reversed: structure, method, and materi- als were all of them subjected to organi- zation. The mor- phology of the continu- ity, form, a- lone was free. Draw- ing a straight line between this sit- uation and that presented
by the later
work, the deduc-
tion might be made
that there is a
tendency in
my composi-
tion means away
from ideas
of order towards
no ideas
of order. And
though when exam-
ined the histo-
ry would probab-
ly not read as
a straight line, re-
cent works, begin-
ning with the Mu-sic of Changes, support the ac- curacy of this deduction. ¶For, in the Mu-sic of Changes, the note-to-note procedure, the method, is the function of chance operations. And the structure, though planned precise- ly as those of the Sonatasand Interludes, and more thorough- ly since it en- compassed the whole span of the com- position, was only a se- ries of numbers, three, five, six and three quarters, six and three quarters, five, three and one eighth, which became, on the one hand, the number of units within each section, and, on the other, number of meas- ures of four-four within each u- nit. At each small structural di- vision in the Music of Chan-ges, at the be- ginning, for ex- ample, and a-
gain at the fourth
and ninth measures
and so on, chance
operations
determined sta-
bility or
change of tempo.
Thus, by intro-
ducing the ac-
tion of method
into the bod-
y of the struc-
ture, and these two
opposed in terms
of order and
freedom, that struc-
ture became in-
determinate:
it was not pos-
sible to know the
total time-length
of the piece un-
til the final
chance opera-
tion, the last toss
of coins af-
fecting the rate
of tempo, had
been made. Being
indetermi-
nate, though still pres-
ent, it became
apparent that
structure was not
necessary,
even though it had
certain uses.
¶One of these u-
ses was the de-
termination
of density,
the determi-
nation, that is,
of how many
of the poten-
tially present
eight lines, each com-
posed of sounds and
silences, were
actually
to be present
within a giv-
en small structur-
al part. ¶Anoth-
er use of the
structure affect-
ed the charts of
sounds and silen-
ces, amplitudes,
durations, po-
tentially ac-
tive in the con-
tinuity.
These twenty-four
charts, eight for sounds
and silences,
eight for ampli-
tudes, eight for du-
rations, were, through-
out the course of
a single struc-
tural unit, half
of them mobile
and half of them
immobile. Mo-
bile meant that once
any of the
elements in
a chart was used
it disappeared
to be replaced
by a new one.
Immobile meant
that though an el-
ement in a
chart had been used,
it remained to
be used again.
At each unit
structural point,
a chance oper-
ation deter-
mined which of the
charts, numbers one,
three, five, and sev-
en or numbers
two, four, six, and
eight, were mobile
and which of the
charts were immo-
bile—not changing.
¶The structure, there-
fore, was in these
respects useful.
Furthermore, it
determined the
beginning and
ending of the
composition-
al process. But
this process, had
it in the end
brought about a
division of
parts the time-lengths
of which were pro-
portional to
the origi-
nal series of
numbers, would have
been extraordi-
nary. And the
presence of the
mind as a rul-
ing factor, e-
ven by such an
extraordina-
ry eventu-
ality, would
not have been es-
tablished. For what
happened came a-
bout only through
the tossing of
coins. ¶It be-
came clear, therefore,
I repeat, that
structure was not
necessary.
And, in Musicfor Piano, and subsequent pieces, indeed, structure is no longer a part of the compo- sition means. The view taken is not of an ac- tivity the purpose of which is to inte- grate the oppo- sites, but rather of an activ- ity charac- terized by process and es- sentially
purposeless. The
mind, though stripped
of its right to
control, is still
present. What does
it do, having
nothing to do?
And what happens
to a piece of
music when it
is purposeless-
ly made? ¶What hap-
pens, for instance,
to silence? That
is, how does the
mind’s perception
of it change? For-
merly, silence
was the time lapse
between sounds, use-
ful towards a va-
riety of
ends, among them
that of tasteful
arrangement, where
by separat-
ing two sounds or
two groups of sounds
their differen-
ces or rela-
tionships might re-
ceive emphasis;
or that of ex-
pressivity,
where silences
in a musi-
cal discourse might
provide pause or
punctuation;
or again, that
of architec-
ture, where the in-
troduction or
interruption
of silence might
give defini-
tion either to
a predeter-
mined structure or
to an organ-
ically de-
veloping one.
Where none of these
or other goals
is present, si-
lence becomes some-
thing else—not si-
lence at all, but
sounds, the ambi-
ent sounds. The na-
ture of these is
unpredicta-
ble and changing.
These sounds (which are
called silence on-
ly because they
do not form part
of a musi-
cal intention)
may be depen-
ded upon to
exist. The world
teems with them, and
is, in fact, at
no point free of
them. He who has
entered an an-
echoic cham-
ber, a room made
as silent as
technologi-
cally possible,
has heard there two
sounds, one high, one
low—the high the
listener’s ner-
vous system in
operation,
the low his blood
in circul-
ation. There are, dem-
onstrably, sounds
to be heard and
forever, giv-
en ears to hear.
Where these ears are
in connection
with a mind that
has nothing to
do, that mind is
free to enter
into the act
of listening,
hearing each sound
just as it is,
not as a phe-
nomenon more
or less approx-
imating a
preconception.
¶What’s the histo-
ry of the chan-
ges in my com-
position means
with particu-
lar reference
to sounds? I had
in mind when I
chose the sounds for
Construction inMetal that they should be sixteen for each player. The number six- teen was also that of the num- ber of measures of four-four in each unit of the rhythmic struc- ture. In the case of the structure this number was divided four, three, two, three, four; in the case of the materi- als the gamuts of sixteen sounds were divided into four groups of four. The plan, as preconceived, was to use four of the sounds in the first sixteen measures, intro- ducing in each succeeding struc- tural unit four more until the exposi- tion involving all sixteen and lasting through the first four units was completed. The subsequent parts, three, two, three, four, were composed
as develop-
ment of this in-
itial situ-
ation. In ac-
tuality,
this simple plan
was not real-
ized, although it
was only re-
cently that I
became fully
aware that it
was not. I had
known all along
that one of the
players used three
Japanese tem-
ple gongs rather
than four, but the
fact that only
three of these rel-
atively rare
instruments were
then availa-
ble to me, to-
gether with the
attachment I
felt towards their sound,
had convinced me
of the rightness
of this change in
number. More se-
rious, however,
it seems to
me now, was the
effect of beat-
ers: playing cow-
bells first with rub-
ber and then with
metal multi-
plied by two the
number of sounds
actually
used. Sirenlike
piano trills
which sound as one
were counted as
two. Various
other devi-
ations from the
original
plan could be dis-
covered on an-
alysis: for
instance, the ad-
dition of met-
al thundersheets
for background noise
bringing the num-
ber sixteen, for
those players who
enjoyed it
to seventeen.
One might conclude
that in compos-
ing Constructionin Metal the organiza- tion of sounds was imperfectly realized. Or he might conclude that the compos- er had not ac- tually lis- tened to the sounds he used, ¶I have already com- pared the selec- tion of the sounds for the Sona-tas and Inter-ludes to a se- lection of shells while walking a- long a beach. They are therefore a collection ex- hibiting taste. Their number was increased by use of the unacorda, this ped- al bringing a- bout altera- tions of timbre and frequency for many of the prepared keys. In terms of pitch, how- ever, there is no change from the sounds of the Con-struction. In both cases a stat- ic gamut of sounds is present- ed, no two oc- taves repeating relations. How- ever, one could hear interest- ing differen- ces between cer- tain of these sounds. On depressing a key, sometimes a single fre- quency was heard. In other cas- es depressing a key produced an interval; in still others an aggregate of pitches and timbres. Noticing the nature of this gamut led to selecting a comparable one for the String Quartet: the
inclusion there
of rigidly
scored convention-
al harmonies
is a matter
of taste, from which
a conscious con-
trol was absent.
Before writing
the Music ofChanges, two piec- es were written which also used gamuts of sounds: single sounds, doub- le sounds and oth- ers more numer- ous, some to be played simultan- eously, oth- ers successiv- ely in time. These pieces were Six-teen Dances and Concerto forPrepared Pia-no and ChamberOrchestra. The elements of the gamuts were arranged unsys- tematically in charts and the method of composition involved moves on these charts anal- agous to those used in construct- ing a magic square. Charts were al- so used for the Music of Chang-es, but in con- trast to the meth- od which involved chance opera- tions, these charts were subjected to a rational control: of the sixty-four el- ements in a square chart eight times eight (made in this way in order to interpret as sounds the co- in oracle of the Chinese Book of Changes) thirty-two were sounds, thirty-two silences. The thirty-two sounds were arranged in two squares one a- bove the other, each four by four. Whether the charts were mobile or immobile, all twelve tones were pres- ent in any four elements of a given chart, whether a line of the chart was read hori- zontally or vertically. Once this dodec- aphonic re- quirement was sat- isfied, noises and repeti- tions of tones were used with freedom.
One may conclude
from this that in
the Music ofChanges the ef- fect of the chance operations on the structure
(making very
apparent its
anachronis-
tic character)
was balanced by
a control of
the materials.
Charts remain in
the Imagi-nary LandscapeNumber IV, and in the WilliamsMix, but, due to the radios of the first piece and the librar- y of record- ed sounds of the second, and for no other rea- son, no twelve-tone control was used. The question “How do we need to cautiously pro- ceed in dual- istic terms?” was not consciously answered until the Music forPiano. In that piece notes were determined by imperfections in the paper upon which the music was writ- ten. The number of imperfec- tions was deter- mined by chance.
The origi-
nal notation
is in ink, and
the actual
steps that were tak-
en in compo-
sition have been
described in an
article in
Die Reihe. ¶Though in the Musicfor Piano I have affirmed the absence of the mind as a ruling agent from the structure and method of the composing means, its presence with regard to material is made clear on examining the sounds themselves: they are only single tones of the convention- al grand pia- no, played at the keyboard, plucked or muted on the strings, together with noises in- side or outside the piano construction. The limited na- ture of this u- niverse of pos- sibilities makes the events themselves compa- rable to the first attempts at speech of a child or the fumblings about of a blind man. The mind reappears as the agent which established the boundaries with- in which this small play took place. Some- thing more far-reach- ing is neces- sary: a com- posing of sounds within a u- niverse predi- cated upon the sounds themselves
rather than up-
on the mind which
can envisage
their coming in-
to being. ¶Sounds,
as we know, have
frequency, am-
plitude, dura-
tion, timbre, and in
a composi-
tion, an order
of succession.
Five lines repre-
senting these five
characteris-
tics may be drawn
in India ink
upon trans-
parent plastic
squares. Upon an-
other such square
a point may be
inscribed. Placing
the square with the
lines over the
square with the point,
a determi-
nation may be
made as to the
physical na-
ture of a sound
and its place with-
in a deter-
mined program sim-
ply by dropping
a perpendi-
cular from the
point to the line
and measuring
according to
any method
of measurement.
Larger points will
have the meaning
of intervals
and largest points
that of aggre-
gates. In order
to make the sev-
eral measure-
ments necessar-
y for inter-
vals and aggre-
gates, further squares
having five lines
are made and the
meaning of an-
y of the lines
is left unde-
termined, so that
a given one
refers to an-
y of the five
characteris-
tics. These squares are
square so that they
may be used in
any posi-
tion with respect
to one anoth-
er. This describes
the situa-
tion obtaining
in a recent
composition,
Variations, the composing means itself one of the eighty- four occurring in the part for piano of Concert for Pi-ano and Or-chestra. In this situation, the universe within which the action is to take place is not preconceived. Fur- thermore, as we know, sounds are e- vents in a field of possibil- ities, not on- ly at the dis- crete points conven- tions have favored. The notation of Varia-tions departs from music and im- itates the phys- ical real- ity. ¶It is now my inten- tion to relate the history of the changes with regard to duration of sounds in my com- posing means. Be- yond the fact that in the Construc-tion in Metal there was a con- trol of dura- tion patterns par- allel to that of the number of sounds chosen, nothing uncon- ventional took place. Quantities related through multiplica- tion by two or addition of one-half togeth- er with grupet- tos of three, five, seven, and nine were present. The same holds for the Sonatas andInterludes, though no rhythmic pat- terns were ration- ally controlled. In the String Quar-tet the rhythmic interest drops, movements being nearly charac- terized by the predominance of a single quantity. Not until the Mu-sic of Changes do the quantities and their no- tation change. They are there measured in space, a quar- ter note equal- ling two and one- half centime- ters. This made pos- sible the no- tation of a fraction, for ex- ample one-third of an eighth, with- out the neces- sity of no- tating the re- mainder of the fraction, the re- maining two-thirds, following the same example. This possibil- ity is di- rectly anal- ogous to the practice of cut- ting magnetic tape. In the du- ration charts of the Music ofChanges there were sixty-four el- ements, all of them durations since they were both
applicable
to sound and si-
lence (each of which
had thirty-two
elements). These
were segmented
(for example
one-half plus one-
third of an eighth
plus six-sevenths
of a quarter)
and were expres-
sible wholly
or in part. This
segmentation
was a practi-
cal measure tak-
en to avoid
the writing of
an impossi-
ble situa-
tion which might a-
rise during a
high density
structural a-
rea due to
the chance oper-
ations. ¶The same
segmentation
of durations
took place in the
Williams Mix, since a maximum of eight machines and loudspeakers had been pre-es- tablished. When the density rose from one to six- teen, it was of- ten necessar- y to express durations by their smallest parts, there being no room left on the tape for the larg- er segments. ¶Ex- act measurement and notation
of durations
is in real-
ity mental:
imaginar-
y exacti-
tude. In the case
of tape, many
circumstances
enter which ev-
er so slightly,
but nonetheless
profoundly, al-
ter the inten-
tion (even though
it was only
the carrying out
of an action
indicated
by chance oper-
ations). Some of
these circumstan-
ces are the ef-
fects of weather
upon the ma-
terial; others
follow from hu-
man frailty—
the inabil-
ity to read
a ruler and
make a cut at
a given point—
still others are
due to mechan-
ical causes,
eight machines not
running at pre-
cisely the same
speed. ¶Given these
circumstances,
one might be in-
spired towards greater
heights of dura-
tion control or
he might renounce
the need to con-
trol durations
at all. In Mu-sic for Pia-no I took the latter course. Struc- ture no longer being present, that piece took place in any length of time whatso- ever, accord- ing to the ex- igencies of an occasion. The duration of single sounds was therefore al- so left inde- terminate. The notation took the form of whole notes in space, the space suggesting but not measur- ing time. Noises were crotchets with- out stems. ¶When a performance of Music for Pi-ano involves more than one pi- anist, as it may from two to twenty, the suc- cession of sounds becomes complete- ly indeter- minate. Though each page is read from left to right con- ventionally, the combina- tion is unpre- dictable in terms of succes- sion. ¶The histo- ry of changes with reference to timbre is short. In the Construc-tion in Metal four sounds had a single timbre; while the prepared pi- ano of the Sonatas andInterludes pro- vided by its nature a klang-farbenmelo-die. This inter- est in changing timbres is evi- dent in the StringQuartet. But this matter of tim- bre, which is large- ly a question of taste, was first radically changed for me in the Imagi-nary LandscapeNumber IV. I had, I confess, never enjoyed the sound of ra- dios. This piece opened my ears
to them, and was
essentially
a giving up
of personal
taste about timbre.
I now frequent-
ly compose with
the radio
turned on, and my
friends are no long-
er embarrassed
when visiting
them I inter-
rupt their recep-
tions. Several
other kinds of
sound have been dis-
tasteful to me:
the works of Bee-
thoven, Ital-
ian bel can-to, jazz, and the vibraphone. I used Beethoven in the WilliamsMix, jazz in the Imaginar-y Landscape Num-ber V, bel can-to in the re- cent part for voice in the Concertfor Pianoand Orchestra. It remains for me to come to terms with the vib- raphone. In oth- er words, I find my taste for timbre
lacking in ne-
cessity, and
I discover
that in the pro-
portion I give
it up, I find
I hear more and
more accurate-
ly. Beethoven
now is a sur-
prise, as accept-
able to the
ear as a cow-
bell. What are the
orchestral timbres
of the Concertfor Pianoand Orchestra? It is impos- sible to pre- dict, but this may be said: they in- vite the timbres of jazz, which more than serious music has explored the possibili- ties of instru- ments. ¶With tape and music-synthe- sizers, action with the over- tone structure of sounds can be less a matter of taste and more thor- oughly an ac- tion in a field of possibil- ities. The no- tation I have described for Var-iations deals with it as such. ¶The early works have beginnings, middles, and end- ings. The later ones do not. They begin any- where, last any length of time, and involve more or fewer instru- ments and players. They are therefore not preconceived objects, and to approach them as objects is to utterly miss
the point. They are
occasions for
experience,
and this exper-
ience is not
only received
by the ears but
by the eyes too.
An ear alone
is not a be-
ing. I have no-
ticed listening
to a record
that my attention
moves to a
moving object
or a play of
light, and at a
rehearsal of
the Williams Mix last May when all eight machines were in opera- tion the atten- tion of those pres- ent was engaged by a sixty- year-old pian- o tuner who was busy tun- ing the instru- ment for the eve- ning’s concert. It becomes evi- dent that music itself is an ideal sit- uation, not a real one. The mind may be used either to ig- nore ambient sounds, pitches oth- er than the eight- y-eight, dura- tions which are not counted, timbres which are unmusi- cal or distaste- ful, and in gen- eral to con- trol and under- stand an avail- able exper- ience. Or the mind may give up its desire to improve on cre- ation and func- tion as a faith- ful receiver of experi- ence. ¶I have not yet told any stories and yet when I give a talk I gener- ally do. The subject certain- ly suggests my telling something irrelevant
but my inclin-
ation is to
tell something apt.
That reminds me:
Several years
ago I was
present at a
lecture given
by Dr. Dai-
setz Teitaro
Suzuki. He
spoke quietly
when he spoke. Some-
times, as I was
telling a friend
yesterday eve-
ning, an airplane
would pass over-
head. The lecture
was at Colum-
bia Uni-
versity and
the campus is
directly in
line with the de-
parture from La
Guardia of
planes bound for the
west. When the wea-
ther was good, the
windows were o-
pen: a plane
passing above drowned
out Dr. Dai-
setz Teitaro
Suzuki. Nev-
ertheless, he
never raised his
voice, never paused,
and never in-
formed his listen-
ers of what they
missed of the lec-
ture, and no one
ever asked him
what he had said
while the airplanes
passed above. Any-
way, he was
explaining one
day the meaning
of a Chinese
character—Yu,
I believe it
was—spending the
whole time explain-
ing it and yet
its meaning as
close as he could
get to it in
English was “un-
explainable.”
Finally he
laughed and then said,
“Isn’t it strange
that having come
all the way from
Japan I spend
my time explain-
ing to you that
which is not to
be explained?” ¶That
was not the stor-
y I was go-
ing to tell when
I first thought I
would tell one, but
it reminds me
of another.
Years ago when
I was study-
ing with Arnold
Schoenberg someone
asked him to ex-
plain his technique
of twelve-tone com-
position. His
reply was im-
mediate: “That
is none of your
business.” ¶Now
I remember
the story I
was going to
tell when I first
got the ide-
a to tell one.
I hope I can
tell it well. Sev-
eral men, three
as a matter of
fact, were out
walking one day,
and as they were
walking along
and talking one
of them noticed
another man
standing on a
hill ahead of
them. He turned to
his friends and said,
“Why do you think
that man is stand-
ing up there on
that hill?” One said,
“He must be up
there because it’s
cooler there and
he’s enjoying
the breeze.” He turned
to another
and repeated
his question, “Why
do you think that
man’s standing up
there on that hill?”
The second said,
“Since the hill is
elevated
above the rest
of the land, he
must be up there
in order to
see something in
the distance.” And
the third said, “He
must have lost his
friend and that is
why he is stand-
ing there alone
on that hill.” Af-
ter some time walk-
ing along, the
men came up the
hill and the one
who had been stand-
ing there was still
there: standing there.
They asked him to
say which one was
right concerning
his reason for
standing where he
was standing. ¶“What
reasons do you
have for my stand-
ing here?” he asked.
“We have three,” they
answered. “First, you
are standing up
here because it’s
cooler here and
you are enjoy-
ing the breeze. Second,
since the hill
is eleva-
ted above the
rest of the land,
you are up here
in order to
see something in
the distance. Third,
you have lost your
friend and that is
why you are stand-
ing here alone
on this hill. We
have walked this way;
we never meant
to climb this hill;
now we want an
answer: Which one
of us is right?”
¶The man answered,
“I just stand.” ¶When
I was studying
with Schoenberg
one day as he was
writing some
counterpoint to
show the way to
do it, he used
an eraser.
And then while he
was doing this
he said, “This end
of the pencil
is just as im-
portant as the
other end.” I
have several
times in the course
of this lecture
mentioned ink. Com-
posing, if it
is writing notes,
is then actu-
ally writing,
and the less one
thinks it’s thinking
the more it be-
comes what it is:
writing. Could mu-
sic be composed
(I do not mean
improvised) not
writing it in
pencil or ink?
The answer is
no doubt Yes and
the changes in
writing are pro-
phetic. The So-natas and In-terludes were com- posed by playing the piano, listening to differences, making a choice, roughly writing it in pencil; later this sketch
was copied, but
again in pen-
cil. Finally
an ink manuscript
was made care-
fully. The Mu-sic of Changes was composed in almost the same way. With one change: the origi- nal pencil sketch was made exac- tly, an era- ser used whenev- er necessar- y, elimin- ating the need for a neat pen- cil copy. In the case of the Imaginar-y Landscape Num-ber IV, the first step of playing the instrument was elimin- ated. The oth- ers kept. Musicfor Piano was written di- rectly in ink.
II. Indeterminacy
The excessively small type in the following pages is an attempt to emphasize the intentionally pontifical character of this lecture.
This is a lecture on composition which is indeterminate with respect to its performance. The Klavierstück XI by Karlheinz Stockhausen is an example. The Art of the Fugue by Johann Sebastian Bach is an example. In The Art of the Fugue, structure, which is the division of the whole into parts; method, which is the note-to-note procedure; and form, which is the expressive content, the morphology of the continuity, are all determined. Frequency and duration characteristics of the material are also determined. Timbre and amplitude characteristics of the material, by not being given, are indeterminate. This indeterminacy brings about the possibility of a unique overtone structure and decibel range for each performance of The Art of the Fugue. In the case of the Klavierstück XI, all the characteristics of the material are determined, and so too is the note-to-note procedure, the method. The division of the whole into parts, the structure, is determinate. The sequence of these parts, however, is indeterminate, bringing about the possibility of a unique form, which is to say a unique morphology of the continuity, a unique expressive content, for each performance.
The function of the performer, in the case of The Art of the Fugue, is comparable to that of someone filling in color where outlines are given. He may do this in an organized way which may be subjected successfully to analysis. (Transcriptions by Arnold Schoenberg and Anton Webern give examples pertinent to this century.) Or he may perform his function of colorist in a way which is not consciously organized (and therefore not subject to analysis)—either arbitrarily, feeling his way, following the dictates of his ego; or more or less unknowingly, by going inwards with reference to the structure of his mind to a point in dreams, following, as in automatic writing, the dictates of his subconscious mind; or to a point in the collective unconscious of Jungian psychoanalysis, following the inclinations of the species and doing something of more or less universal interest to human beings; or to the “deep sleep” of Indian mental practice—the Ground of Meister Eckhart—identifying there with no matter what eventuality. Or he may perform his function of colorist arbitrarily, by going outwards with reference to the structure of his mind to the point of sense perception, following his taste; or more or less unknowingly by employing some operation exterior to his mind: tables of random numbers, following the scientific interest in probability; or chance operations, identifying there with no matter what eventuality.
The function of the performer in the case of the Klavierstück XI is not that of a colorist but that of giving form, providing, that is to say, the morphology of the continuity, the expressive content. This may not be done in an organized way: for form unvitalized by spontaneity brings about the death of all the other elements of the work. Examples are provided by academic studies which copy models with respect to all their compositional elements: structure, method, material, and form. On the other hand, no matter how rigorously controlled or conventional the structure, method, and materials of a composition are, that composition will come to life if the form is not controlled but free and original. One may cite as examples the sonnets of Shakespeare and the haikus of Basho. How then in the case of the Klavierstück XI may the performer fulfill his function of giving form to the music? He must perform his function of giving form to the music in a way which is not consciously organized (and therefore not subject to analysis), either arbitrarily, feeling his way, following the dictates of his ego, or more or less unknowingly, by going inwards with reference to the structure of his mind to a point in dreams, following, as in automatic writing, the dictates of his subconscious mind; or to a point in the collective unconscious of Jungian psychoanalysis, following the inclinations of the species and doing something of more or less universal interest to human beings; or to the “deep sleep” of Indian mental practice—the Ground of Meister Eckhart—identifying there with no matter what eventuality. Or he may perform his function of giving form to the music arbitrarily, by going outwards with reference to the structure of his mind to the point of sense perception, following his taste; or more or less unknowingly by employing some operation exterior to his mind: tables of random numbers, following the scientific interest in probability; or chance operations, identifying there with no matter what eventuality.
However, due to the presence in the Klavierstück XI of the two most essentially conventional aspects of European music—that is to say, the twelve tones of the octave (the frequency characteristic of the material) and regularity of beat (affecting the element of method in the composing means), the performer—in those instances where his procedure follows any dictates at all (his feelings, his automatism, his sense of universality, his taste)—will be led to give the form aspects essentially conventional to European music. These instances will predominate over those which are unknowing where the performer wishes to act in a way consistent with the composition as written. The form aspects essentially conventional to European music are, for instance, the presentation of a whole as an object in time having a beginning, a middle, and an ending, progressive rather than static in character, which is to say possessed of a climax or climaxes and in contrast a point or points of rest.
The indeterminate aspects of the composition of the Klavierstück XI do not remove the work in its performance from the body of European musical conventions. And yet the purpose of indeterminacy would seem to be to bring about an unforseen situation. In the case of Klavierstück XI, the use of indeterminacy is in this sense unnecessary since it is ineffective. The work might as well have been written in all of its aspects determinately. It would lose, in this case, its single unconventional aspect: that of being printed on an unusually large sheet of paper which, together with an attachment that may be snapped on at several points enabling one to stretch it out flat and place it on the music rack of a piano, is put in a cardboard tube suitable for safekeeping or distribution through the mails.
This is a lecture on composition which is indeterminate with respect to its performance. The Intersection 3 by Morton Feldman is an example. The Music of Changes is not an example. In the Music of Changes, structure, which is the division of the whole into parts; method, which is the note-to-note procedure; form, which is the expressive content, the morphology of the continuity; and materials, the sounds and silences of the composition, are all determined. Though no two performances of the Music of Changes will be identical (each act is virgin, even the repeated one, to refer to René Char’s thought), two performances will resemble one another closely. Though chance operations brought about the determinations of the composition, these operations are not available in its performance. The function of the performer in the case of the Music of Changes is that of a contractor who, following an architect’s blueprint, constructs a building. That the Music of Changes was composed by means of chance operations identifies the composer with no matter what eventuality. But that its notation is in all respects determinate does not permit the performer any such identification: his work is specifically laid out before him. He is therefore not able to perform from his own center but must identify himself insofar as possible with the center of the work as written. The Music of Changes is an object more inhuman than human, since chance operations brought it into being. The fact that these things that constitute it, though only sounds, have come together to control a human being, the performer, gives the work the alarming aspect of a Frankenstein monster. This situation is of course characteristic of Western music, the masterpieces of which are its most frightening examples, which when concerned with humane communication only move over from Frankenstein monster to Dictator.