Читать книгу Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience - P. M. S. Hacker - Страница 18
ОглавлениеPart I Philosophical Problems in Neuroscience: Their Historical and Conceptual Roots
Preliminaries to Part I
1 Philosophical Problems in Neuroscience: Their Historical Roots
The more than two thousand years of the history of what became known as cognitive neuroscience shows that the discipline is grounded in correlations of human behaviour, reflecting psychological powers such as seeing, hearing, remembering, etc, with areas of the brain and their function. Such correlations are often erroneously taken to show that psychological attributes pertain to parts of the brain (the occipital cortex perceives, the hippocampus remembers), whereas the correlations are with the behaving human being, who perceives and remembers.
Galen
In the second century ad Galen identified the proper functioning of the enkephalon which is necessary for the mental powers of humans. This was based on careful clinical observations of the many injured charioteers and gladiators he had access to, followed by careful pathological examination of their bodies. Galen may be thought of as the initiator of what became known as the clinico-pathological procedure in neurology, whereby correlations are sought between abnormal behaviour and a diseased state of the body. In this case Galen observed that the ability to think and reason were impaired when damage had occurred to the brain, but not to other parts of the body. Unfortunately, when he passed on to the question of what particular parts of the brain were necessary for reasoning he departed from the clinical-pathological method, and guessed that it was the ventricles, considering the cortex as merely the wall of the ventricles.
Nemesius
In the fourth century ad Nemesius believed he could affirm and extend Galen’ s claim that the ventricles were correlated with possession of human powers using the clinico-pathological approach. He claimed to show that injury or disease to each of the ventricles led to behavioural deficits indicative of the failure of a particular power. For example, if the front ventricles are harmed then the senses are abnormal but thought remains normal. This example of incorrect conclusions drawn through application of the clinic-pathological technique indicates how difficult the search for correlations can be, and is manifest even in the search for the primary visual cortex, for which a consensus was reached only towards the end of the nineteenth century.
Thomas Willis
In the seventeenth century Thomas Willis, a master of the clinico-pathological technique, showed that it is the cortex of the brain, not the ventricles, that is correlated with the possession and exercise of psychological powers. Willis often studied the behaviour of his patients over many years, writing up detailed reports of abnormal behaviour indicative of the failure of a psychological power or a group of powers, and then correlating these with abnormalities of the cortex revealed on dissection at autopsy, all of which he published. Perhaps the most spectacular of these was his identification of congenital mental disabilities with clear cortical abnormalities (Figure 1). But even more specific behavioural maladies, such as long-standing one-sided paralysis, were correlated at autopsy, in this case with unilateral degeneration of the cerebral peduncle. It was the quality of the careful observations that Willis made which allowed him to identify cortical lesions as opposed to those organs such as the spleen and lungs that were claimed by others to be the basis of disorders of behaviour. By the time Willis had completed his clinico-pathological correlations, together with detailed anatomical drawings, there was no doubt that a normal cortex was necessary for normal behaviour. But although the ventricles had been displaced as centres of interest in this regard, the question of which part(s) of a normal functioning cortex are correlated with the behavioural manifestations of particular psychological powers had not been elucidated.
Figure 1 Illustrations from Cerebri Anatome of Thomas Willis, showing on the left the underside of a normal human brain and on the right of a brain from a person suffering from congenital mental weakness. Reproduced with the permission of the library of St John’s College, Oxford
Clinico-pathological correlations in the nineteenth century
The nineteenth century saw a flowering of the clinico-pathological correlation of cortical areas with psychological powers, such as vision and speech. It might seem straightforward to identify abnormal behaviour(s) uniquely due to the loss of a psychological power, but this is not necessarily so, as behaviour exhibits such a variety of different forms.1 Furthermore, identifying at an autopsy the unique site of a lesion or degeneration is difficult at any time, let alone with no more than the tools available in the nineteenth century. Even when considering a comparatively straightforward power in this regard, such as vision, it took fifty years before the primary visual cortex was agreed upon as located in the occipital lobe.2 Nevertheless, significant progress was made by Broca, as well as Fritsch, Hitzig and others, together with Sherrington’ s researches on primates.
Single neuron investigations and fMRI in the twentieth century:primacy of behaviour
In the twentieth century the correlations revealed following careful application of the clinico-pathological technique were followed by neuroscientific investigations into the neural mechanisms operating within the identified cortical areas. The introduction of new techniques by Adrian and Eccles in the first half of the twentieth century allowed for a new level of spatial resolution relating psychological powers and cortical function, namely that of a neuron within the already identified cortical area, such as those of Blakemore in the visual occipital cortex. However, these new technologies and those introduced later in the century, such as functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI), did not change the basic logic that in order to understand the function of the cortex, whether at the level of anatomical parts or that of single neurons, correlations must be made with that of the experiencing, behaving animal or human that is under study. Of course, study of cellular mechanisms, such as excitatory synaptic transmission, can be understood at the mechanistic level without reference to behaviour, but to understand their relevance within a particular cortical region requires reference through correlations with the behaviour and experiences of the animal.
Misascription of psychological attributes to parts of the cortex andto neurons
The twentieth century saw the growth of the misascription of psychological powers to parts of the cortex and to neurons rather than to the experiencing, behaving human possessing the cortex with its neurons. The experimental attempt over the past two thousand years to understand the functions of the brain have matured along the only path that is logically possible, namely: seeking correlations of the kind described above. However, the realization of this has been increasingly lost over the history of neuroscience to the present day. This is manifest in researchers asserting that the particular cortical area or neuron under study is the experiencing agent, forgetting that it is the correlations of that area/neuron with human experience and behaviour that identified the region under consideration in the first place. It might be argued that Blakemore, Zeki, Damasio, Tononi and many others are simply ascribing psychological predicates to different cortical areas and their neurons as a convenient shorthand, but an appraisal of their work shows that not to be the case. Clearly this is untenable.
2 Philosophical Problems in Neuroscience: Their Conceptual Roots
The history of neuroscience shows that our understanding of cortical function is founded of necessity on correlations with human behaviour and experience. We now consider a different approach, based on logico-grammatical grounds, to the question of whether psychological attributes (seeing, thinking, remembering, etc.) can be attributed to a part of the cortex, either an anatomical part or a group of neurons.
Psychological attributes are attributes of the sentient creature as a whole
This approach was initiated by Aristotle in the fourth century bc. Aristotle states in his De Anima that ‘To say that the psuche¯ is angry is as if one were to say that the psuche¯ weaves or builds. For it is surely better not to say that the psuche¯ pities, learns, or thinks, but that the man does these things with his psuche¯.’ Here Aristotle is emphasizing that pitying, learning and thinking can be sensibly attributed only to human beings, not to some principle of life that informs their body, namely the psuche¯ (sometimes incorrectly translated as ‘soul’). In the nineteenth century Lewes restated Aristotle’ s conception in its modern form. In his The Physical Basis of Mind (1891) he states that ‘It is the man and not the brain, that thinks; it is the organism as a whole and not one organ that feels and acts.’ In the twentieth century Wittgenstein offers the same thought in his Philosophical Investigations (1953), ‘Only of a living human being and what resembles (behaves like) a living human being can one say: it has sensations, it sees; is blind; hears; is deaf; is conscious or unconscious.’
Aristotle, Lewes and Wittgenstein are pointing out that there are no logico-linguistic grounds for attributing psychological predicates to the brain, parts of the brain, or indeed any other parts of the body, rather than to behaving human beings. The logic of part/whole relations is known as mereology. The misattribution of psychological predicates by many neuroscientists we call the mereological fallacy in neuroscience. The conceptual confusions arising from this fallacy, together with the fact that the history of cognitive neuroscience is a search for correlations with behaviour, makes clear that it is humans that experience, not their brains or parts of their brains.