Читать книгу Bioethics - Группа авторов - Страница 46
Prenatal Screening, Sex Selection, and Cloning
ОглавлениеAs our knowledge of genetics expands, prospective parents are increasingly given the opportunity to make use of this knowledge, to prevent the birth of genetically compromised children. Here it is important to note that prevention need not involve abortion or the destruction of preimplantation embryos. At‐risk parents can avoid having a disabled child by deciding not to have children, by adopting children, or by using donor gametes or embryos.
Is it wrong to bring severely disabled children into the world, if one could avoid doing so? Laura M. Purdy in “Genetics and Reproductive Risk: Can Having Children be Immoral?” gives an affirmative answer. Rejecting the view “that it is morally permissible to conceive individuals so long as we do not expect them to be so miserable that they wish they were dead,” she argues that parents ought to ensure that any children they are going to have, possess “normal health.” While she acknowledges that the notion is vague, she takes it to be sufficient to mark out as wrong the bringing into the world of children who are at risk of having serious genetic afflictions, such as Huntington’s disease.
The notion that there ought to be a sphere of liberty within which prospective parents are free to make reproductive choices is widely accepted. There is, however, disagreement as to whether reproductive liberty has limits, and if it does, where these limits ought to be drawn. Take sex selection. Many jurisdictions allow parents to prevent the birth of children affected by certain genetic diseases, but do not allow them to do this for non‐medical reasons, such as wanting to balance the sex ratio of their children. In a statement entitled “Sex Selection and Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis,” the Ethics Committee of the American Society of Reproductive Medicine indicates the extent to which it shares the concerns behind such laws. The Committee itself does not believe that non‐medical sex selection is so clearly and seriously wrong that it favors the use of the law to prohibit it. Instead, the Committee would stop at discouraging sex selection for non‐medical reasons.
Julian Savulescu and Edgar Dahl respond to the Committee’s statement in their essay “Sex Selection and Preimplantation Diagnosis.” They find its arguments unpersuasive, particularly given that, in Western societies, most people seeking to use sex selection do so not because they value one sex more than the other, but to balance the number of boys and girls in their family.
Those opposing preimplantation genetic diagnosis for the above purpose may, however, have concerns that go beyond the welfare interests of the future child. David King explains “Why We Should Not Permit Embryos to be Selected as Tissue Donors.” He believes that the practice objectifies the child and turns it into a mere tool. This contradicts, he says, the basic Kantian ethical principle that human beings must always be treated as ends, and never merely as a means to an end. Even if the future child will be a much‐loved member of the family, we ought to resist the temptation to allow the selection of embryos as tissue donors because it is yet another step in the objectification of humans and “and the consequences of doing so are … disastrous.”
But is the maxim that we must never regard others solely as a means to an end infringed if the tissue‐matched child is loved and cherished in its own right, as an end? Kant’s maxim provides, as King correctly notes, a plausible account of what is wrong with slavery, but its implication in the present context is far less clear. People generally have children for a variety of reasons: they want a sister for “Ann,” a companion for their old age, a son to continue the blood line, and so on. If tissue‐matching of embryos to save another child were ruled out by the Kantian maxim, would this not also perhaps rule out many other widely accepted reasons for having children as well?
In allowing tissue‐matching of embryos, we are, King holds, proceeding down a slippery slope toward some very bad societal consequences. Critics of this kind of argument might question, however, whether the bad consequences at the bottom of the slope are truly bad, or as bad as they are made out to be. They may also ask whether the slope is really so slippery and if sound laws and public policies would not arrest any possible slide.
For many people reproductive human cloning is one of the bad consequences that lie at the bottom of the slippery slope. When the existence of the sheep “Dolly” (the first mammal to owe its existence to somatic cell nuclear transfer, or cloning) was announced in 1997, there was swift world‐wide reaction. People feared that the cloning of humans would not be far away. Only 24 hours after the world knew of Dolly’s existence, a bill outlawing human cloning was announced in New York State, and a few days later, then US President Clinton banned federal funding for research into it.
Michael Tooley examines this issue in “The Moral Status of Human Cloning: Neo‐Lockean Persons versus Human Embryos.” In earlier editions of this Anthology, we included an article by the same author, first published in 1998. In that earlier article, Tooly distinguished between the questions of whether reproductive human cloning is in principle morally acceptable and whether it is acceptable at the present time, given current scientific knowledge and understanding. He then reached the conclusion that the practice was acceptable in principle, but morally problematic, given the state of knowledge at the time. In this new article, specially written for this volume, Tooley notes more recent research that makes it less likely that cloning from an adult would produce a person with reduced life expectancy. In this and other ways, his conclusion is now more open to the acceptability of human reproductive cloning, both in principle and in practice, than it was in his earlier article.