Читать книгу Deficiency and Delinquency: An Interpretation of Mental Testing - James Burt Miner - Страница 16
(d) Allowance may be made for variability.
ОглавлениеThe quantitative definition of intellectual deficiency must be made with careful allowance for irregularities among different mental processes, among different individuals, and among different groups. Theoretically it is possible to place the borderline so low that a case with that degree of deficiency and without removable handicaps would be clearly feeble-minded. The chance that the diagnosis would be mistaken could be reduced to any minimum desired. Above this a wider region of doubtful deficiency could then be stated in similar form. This is the plan that we suggest in attempting the percentage definition. Practically, however, the plan assumes that a suitable allowance can actually be made for these variations and raises a number of problems as to variability which should be considered. Four of these sources of variation are discussed below: (1) the variation due to a limited sample of individuals measured, (2) the variation among different communities, (3) the variations arising from sex, race and social differences, (4) the variation of the same individual from one mental process to another. We do not have the problem of neglecting these variations, but of adequately allowing for them both in the percentage of presumably deficient and in the doubtful region.
(1) Variation among Samples of Individuals Measured. The error introduced by the fact that measurements are made on a limited rather than an unlimited number of individuals, in establishing the standards with a system of tests, can be taken care of statistically fairly well by applying the theory of probability as to the error of a percentage in a single sample. The range of the error can then be indicated on the measurement scale. This supposes, however, that each sample to be measured is taken from a random group and not from a selected group. Allowance for this error of sampling is therefore complicated by the fact that the usual test data have been obtained from groups of school children, even when there has been no further selection within the school group. Data on school children are certainly reliable only within the years of compulsory school attendance. Ordinarily in this country, they are not reliable for children of 14 years of age or over. Moreover, the point of the scale which is reached by the lowest X percentage of school pupils will exclude a slightly larger percentage of all children of corresponding ages, since the idiots and some imbeciles are not sent to the ordinary schools. This slight discrepancy should be kept in mind. The problem of avoiding selected samples among adults is still more difficult; but we found that it was possible in one community at least to measure all the 15-year-olds in the lowest X percentage in certain districts, as we shall note later. By this age, mental processes are probably very much like those of adults, except for the amount of information and practise.
(2) Variation among Different Communities. Under any conception of deficiency it is clear that there are relatively more deficients in some communities than others. The percentage should, of course, not be determined for a small community such as a city or county, but for a state or a nation in order to avoid the difficulty of the difference between communities. It would not interfere with the plan for isolating the lowest X percentage of a state even if that meant isolating 10% in one small community and none in another. Indeed, it might be expected to do just that, when one considers the accumulation of deficiency in certain settlements such as Key has shown (131, p. 63). The data on which the borderline with a measuring scale would be established should, of course, not be obtained from communities known to be unusual in respect to the frequency of deficiency.
Since social failure is our final criterion for judging deficiency, we must further consider that it is easier for a person to survive in one environment than in another: in the country, for example, than in the city. This sort of problem has led to considerable confusion. Goddard remarks: “In consequence of this it happens that a man may be intelligent in one environment and unintelligent in another. It is this point which Binet has illustrated by saying 'A French peasant may be normal in a rural community but feeble-minded in Paris.'” (117, p. 573.) Goddard then goes on to suppose that a delinquent with the intelligence of a sixteen year old may be “defective” because he happens “to have got into an environment that requires a twenty-year-old intelligence.” The suggestion that a criminal might be excused on the ground of deficiency because he happened to fall among bad companions is a reductio ad absurdum. Clearly environment must be defined as ordinary environment, available environment or by some similar concept, or else the definition of deficiency loses all significance. In another place Goddard more properly suggests that it would be well to “draw one line at that point below which a person of that intelligence is not desirable or useful in any environment” (117, p. 3).
So long as the care of the feeble-minded is a state problem the percentage of passable intellects would apparently be determined for the available environment in that state. The problem of social care cannot mean that the state should care for college men because they cannot survive among college men or in the station of life into which they may have been born. So long as there are environments within the community where they can survive it is a problem of shifting them in their social habitat, not a problem for social care. The same is true for the low grades of intellect. It is not likely, however, that any portion of the community could absorb many more of the low degree intellects. For the problem of social care for the feeble-minded, the question: What environment will allow this individual to survive? becomes the question: Can he survive in any available environment in his community? It would seem very hazardous to suppose that the different opportunities for survival afforded by different localities in a state would be large enough to care for more than the group of doubtful cases which should be allowed for in a quantitative description of the border region.
(3) The Variation with Sex, Race, and Social Position has been carefully called to attention by Yerkes and Bridges in their studies with the Binet Point Scale (225, Chap. V and VI). It may very well be that not as high ability should be expected of certain groups as of others; as a matter of moral obligation, they are not as responsible for their conduct or their attainments. On the other hand this does not directly affect the question, what lowest percentage of intellects cannot get along in society? When that percentage is determined for the environment available in the community all those who fall within it might even turn out to be of one sex or of one nationality or of one social position, without affecting the question whether they should be cared for by society, or what grade of intellect is not socially passable? Temporary social handicaps, such as lack of familiarity with the language, lack of training, etc., must, of course, be allowed for so far as they affect the individual's test record. Whether the difference of 5% to 10% in the score of pupils born to non-English-speaking families compared to their companions' (225, p. 66) is due to the temporary handicap of language or to a permanent difference is, however, just the problem which the Yerkes and Bridges study does not answer. The fact that the difference is even greater for older children suggests that it may indicate an inborn difference between the groups compared.
A diagnosis of deficiency should not be made until the examiner is able to estimate whether the removal of training or health handicaps would bring the individual above the borderline. So far as known temporary handicaps affect the standard of the test results with groups they should, of course, also be taken into account. On the other hand, it is clear that the borderline which predicts social failure should not be shifted to allow for differences in permanent handicaps whether those be of race, sex or social position.
(4) The Variation among Different Mental Processes. With our present knowledge the most difficult variation for which we must make allowance at the borderline is the variation from one trait or process to another in the same individual. One phase of it was discussed above under “c.” The investigation of Norsworthy throws light on this question. Summarizing her tests she says: “Among idiots there is not an equal lack of mental capacity in all directions. There is something of the same lack of correlation among the traits measured in the case of idiots as there is with ordinary people” (159, p. 68). Again: “The idiots are nearest the central tendency for children in general in the measurements of mental traits which are chiefly tests of maturity, and farther and farther away as measurements are made which are tests of ability to deal with abstract data. They are two and a half times as far from the median for children in general in tests like the genus-species test as they are in tests like the A test or the perception of weight.” Weidensall (60) and Pyle (46) also compare delinquent and normal individuals for different tests, showing a variation with the sort of mental activity compared.
While Norsworthy thus presents evidence of certain specializations of deficiency, she notes, however, that perhaps feeble-mindedness is more typically general than specific and that general deficiency is more important to consider than specific. Even with that test with which her group of retarded and feeble-minded children did best, only 28% of them passed the point which would be excelled by 75% of the children in general. In their worst test only 1% passed this point. It is also to be noticed that those tests in which they most nearly approached ordinary children are for just those simple processes which would be least likely to be of use in the struggle for social existence. As a whole, therefore, there is nothing in her results which shows that any appreciable number of children who were deficient in the average of tested abilities, would have good enough special ability along a few lines to make them socially passable. Indeed, for all that we know at present, the borderline for passable ability in each of our various mental processes might vary quite as much as Norsworthy found, without this variation affecting a prediction of failure based upon the average of a series of tests.
On account of the great attention that has been paid to individual differences in recent years, on account of their importance for diagnosis, for determining the causes of deficiency, and for planning for the training of deficients, we have come almost to the point where we forget the significance of the average as the most common condition with which we have to deal. The lack of complete correlation between abilities of an individual does not make us hesitate to use the concept of his average ability; it should not make us neglect or misunderstand the significance of the position of an individual testing low down on the scale. For the problem of social care the borderline position on a scale is immensely more important than higher ability. It seems advisable, therefore, to define this borderline ability with some suitable allowance for variability in mental processes. It is far safer to judge an individual's chance of survival by his average or general tested ability than by the little knowledge that is as yet available regarding special abilities.
4. Augusta F. Bronner. The Psychology of Special Abilities and Disabilities. Boston, 1917, pp. vii, 269.